You are here:
NZLII >>
Databases >>
New Zealand Human Rights Commission Submissions >>
2018 >>
[2018] NZHRCSub 6
Database Search
| Name Search
| Recent Documents
| Noteup
| LawCite
| Download
| Help
End of Life Choice Bill - Submission to the Justice Committee (Disability Rights Commissioner) [2018] NZHRCSub 6 (11 July 2018)
Last Updated: 15 June 2019

Submission of The Disability
Rights Commissioner on the End of Life Choice Bill
Contact Person:
Paula Tesoriero
Disability Rights Commissioner
New Zealand Human Rights Commission Email:
1
Submission of the Disability Rights Commissioner to the Justice
Select Committee on the End of Life Choice Bill
Introduction and Summary of Position
- The
Human Rights Commission (‘the Commission’) is an independent Crown
Entity. The primary statutory functions of the
Commission include advocating and
promoting respect for human rights and promoting and protecting the full and
equal enjoyment of
human rights by people with
disabilities.
- As
Disability Rights Commissioner, I have a specific statutory responsibility to
lead the work of the Commission in relation to the
priority area of disability
rights.
- In
January 2016 the Commission provided a submission to the Health Select Committee
Inquiry into End of Life Matters (the “2016”
submission). This
explored the human rights principles, legislation and case law relevant to the
issues being considered by the present
committee. The 2016 submission concluded
that a legal framework permitting assistance to be given to a competent
terminally ill adult
to end his or her life (if he or she freely and
autonomously chose to do so) could potentially be implemented
if:1
- It
is developed in a manner consistent with core human rights principles;
and
- Is
accompanied by adequate legal and procedural safeguards to protect vulnerable
members of society; and
- Appropriate
palliative care services are available and remain accessible for
all.
4. Taking into account the Commission’s position above,
and my specific statutory responsibility to the disability community,
my
position is that:
- this
Bill undermines the position of disabled and vulnerable members of our community
and poses significant risks to them, as individuals
and as a group;
- the
proposed safeguards in the Bill are deficient, both procedurally and
substantively, for both terminal and non-terminal
conditions;
- It
is not possible to consider the issue of legalising assistance in dying in
isolation from palliative care service provision and
the current services and
resources available to those who experience serious but non-terminal
conditions.
1 Submission of the New Zealand Human Rights
Commission to the Health Select Committee in relation to its investigation into
End of
Life Matters; 29 January 2016 at para 48.
- These
matters are discussed in more detail below. A copy of the 2016 submission, and a
summary of my recommendations in relation to
key aspects of the current Bill,
are attached as appendices. These should be read in conjunction with this
submission. For the avoidance
of doubt, this submission builds on and does not
replace, the 2016 agreed Commission position on end of life matters. It focusses
on issues specifically affecting the disability community
Human Rights Principles and Scope of the Bill
- In
its 2016 submission the Commission examined human rights principles and
jurisprudence relevant to the issues addressed in the current
Bill. It concluded
that it may be acceptable to permit a competent, adult facing imminent death to
end their life but only if a safe
and appropriate framework could be implemented
and a number of other important prerequisites and safeguards met. It noted the
importance
of the broader societal context in which decisions are made,
including palliative care service provision.
- When
considering the safety and appropriateness of any framework it is also necessary
to consider risks to other members of the community,
as well as those who are
terminally ill and wish to utilise an assisted dying process. The feedback I
have received from members
of the disability community is that it may not be
possible, from their perspective, to identify and implement safeguards that
would
sufficiently protect them from harm. In any case, the procedural
safeguards provided in the Bill fall far short of the mark in terms
of
protecting the interests of even terminally ill individuals for the reasons
outlined later in this submission.
- In
my view, when considering assistance in dying for non-terminal conditions, the
balance must be weighted in favour of protecting
the vulnerable, both as
individuals and as a group. I do not consider that legalising assisted dying in
circumstances other than
imminent death is compatible with a human rights
approach. Such a step poses a substantial risk to vulnerable members of the
community
such as disabled people, older people and disadvantaged/ marginalised
groups.
Specific Concerns About the Inclusion of
“non-terminal” conditions
- The
Bill currently provides that any individual who “suffers from a grievous
or irremediable medical condition” would
be able to access the assisted
dying procedures if he or she is in an advanced state of irreversible decline in
capability and is
experiencing suffering that cannot be relieved in a
manner
that is considered tolerable.
- This
eligibility criteria captures a broad range of illnesses and conditions. It is
possible that relatively common chronic health
conditions, such as diabetes,
heart disease, neurological disorders, intellectual disabilities, autism and
other neuro-disabilities
and regional pain syndromes, if advanced and
sufficiently degenerative, could fall within the Bill’s scope.
Furthermore, the
criteria is not expressly limited to physical conditions. It is
possible that a person experiencing a mental health or psychological
disorder,
such as depression, anorexia or a bi-polar disorder could, in certain
circumstances, be interpreted as fitting the criteria.
- In
addition, the criteria of “unbearable suffering that cannot be relieved in
a manner that is considered tolerable”2 is inherently
subjective and can only be assessed by ascertaining the personal experience and
views of the individual concerned.
It is notable that the criteria is not
limited to the existence of physical pain. There is a real risk that
psychological pain manifested
in feelings of hopelessness, despair or
worthlessness could fall within the criteria. This is a matter of considerable
concern to
the disability community, in particular the implicit message this
aspect of the Bill sends vulnerable and isolated disabled about
the value of
their lives.
- Disabled
New Zealanders make up 24 percent of New Zealand’s overall
population.3 They are marginalised and discriminated against in
almost all areas of life. They face practical and attitudinal barriers that
hinder
their ability to participate fully in society and therefore many
experience poor life outcomes in a range of areas. They often experience
bullying, have difficulty obtaining an education and finding a job and often do
not have access to the supports and resources that
would allow them to take part
in activities and experiences on an equal basis with non-disabled
people.
- Statistics
indicate that disabled people are currently unable to participate in society on
an equal basis with non-disabled people4. For many disabled people,
this means they do not have the same freedom
2 Section 4(f)
3 Disability Survey 2013, Statistics NZ.
4 For example, recent data from Statistics NZ Household
Labourforce Survey 2017 (June Quarter) shows that 42 percent of young disabled
people are not in education, employment, or training compared to 10 percent of
non- disabled young people (he unemployment rate of
disabled people (11.4
percent) is more than double that of non- disabled people (4.5 percent) and only
25.2 percent of disabled people
of working age participate in the labour force
compared to 72.6 percent of non disabled people. Furthermore, data from
Statistics
NZ’s 2016 General Social Survey indicates more disabled people
feel they experience discrimination than non-disabled people
(21.5 percent
compared to 16.5 percent); and significantly more disabled people also feel
lonely most or all of the time (12.7 percent
compared to 5.7 percent).
of choice in their everyday lives. This extends from limitations as to where and
with whom they live
- due to a lack of appropriate housing, support services, and low income –
through to every day decision-making about what
they eat, wear and where they
spend their time. People with intellectual disabilities are particularly
vulnerable in this respect.
They often have decisions made for them, or are
coerced into decisions made in their “best interests”, rather than
being
supported to make decisions that reflect their own will and
preferences.
- “Supported
decision making” means ensuring that disabled people can make their own
decisions. The concept is articulated
in Article 12 of the United Nations
Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities. It enables people to have
control and
choice about their lives and what happens to them. Some disabled
people need assistance so they can express their will and preferences
and make
their own decisions. New Zealand law and practice is not well aligned with
Article 12 and there are many areas where disabled
New Zealanders are not
supported to make their own decisions.
- The
risk of coercion, particularly for people with intellectual disabilities, is of
significant concern in the context of end of life
decisions, particularly given
the gravity – and irreversibility – of a decision to opt for
assisted dying. This lack
of choice, imposed or substituted (instead of
supported) decision- making, and possibility for coercion must be taken into
account
when considering autonomy-based arguments for assisted dying. Many
people with disabilities simply do not enjoy the right to personal
autonomy on
an equal basis to non-disabled people. We must therefore first work towards
ensuring, to the greatest extent possible,
that all people have the same freedom
of choice in life before we consider legislating choice in
death.
- Furthermore,
while proponents of assisted dying claim it is a solely individual choice and
should be left up to each individual to
make decisions about their own lives, it
is misleading to suggest there is no impact on others when people exercise such
choice.
Indeed, there are many laws which limit individual choice to protect the
wider community: the requirement to wear a seatbelt, adhere
to speed limits, and
obligations to pay tax. If we didn’t have such laws, there would be
negative collective impacts on society.
Similarly, someone choosing to end their
life through assisted dying, while personal to that individual, could have
far-reaching
consequences for the people around them. For example, those with
similar medical conditions/prognoses may feel pressured to do the
same.
- Anecdotal
evidence (such as the portrayal of disability in the media, and peoples’
response to those
stories) suggests that many people see disabilities, particularly in more severe
forms, as tragic or
even ‘a fate worse than death’. As with other marginalised groups in
history, disabled people are often perceived as
an ‘other’ ( ie
someone not like “you” or “me”) to be pitied or
avoided.
- Unlike
ethnicity or gender, disability can be seen as a medical issue that requires
management rather than being an integral aspect
of a person’s identity.
While overt hostility to disability exists in our society, the most pressing
issue is societal apathy
or indifference towards the value of disability within
a population. This serves to reinforce negative perceptions about disabled
people and the lives that they lead.
- By
providing a pathway for disabled people to end their lives prematurely through
the enactment of the Bill, Parliament risks sending
a message to all disabled
people and to the wider community that the lives of disabled people are of less
value than non-disabled
people and therefore may not be worth living. This sort
of paradigm contributes to the stigmatisation and exclusion of disabled members
of our community.
- A
distinction can be made between providing choice and options to those who are in
the final stages of a terminal illness and implementing
a pathway for those who
are not imminently facing death, but who believe that they do not wish to
continue living. My position is
that providing the latter group with an assisted
dying option carries significant risks for disabled people and other vulnerable
groups such as older members of our community. Because of the insidious nature
of the risks, they cannot be adequately addressed
through legislative
safeguards.
- In
jurisdictions where euthanasia is available for people without a terminal
illness, it is notable that cases of euthanasia for psychiatric
conditions have
increased. In Belgium, reported cases of the euthanasia of people with
neuropsychiatric conditions increased from
0.8% to 3.9%.5 Similarly,
euthanasia deaths based on psychiatric reasons have also increased in the
Netherlands.6
- Of
further note, a recent study in Oregon found that the most commonly cited
reasons for choosing assisted dying were losses of autonomy
(91.6%) and loss of
dignity (78.6%) rather than inadequate pain management which only contributed to
the decision in 25.2% of cases.7 In other words, most people chose
assisted dying not because they were in insufferable pain, but because they were
afraid
5https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5088089/
6 https://www.ieb-eib.org/en/document/report-2016-euthanasia-in-netherlands-488.html
7 https://jamanetwork.com/journals/jamaoncology/article-abstract/2616352
of losing their independence and dignity. This outcome is concerning from a
disability perspective, as it is indicative of prevailing
attitudes towards the
experiences of disabled people. Many disabled people rely on others for basic
daily living tasks, some of which
such as showering and toileting, may be
perceived to be undignified.
Current Health and Disability Supports and
Resources
- It
is of considerable concern that extensive resources, time and money would be
required to support the implementation of this Bill,
yet there are many areas
where adequate resources are not made available to ensure the full and equal
enjoyment of human rights by
disabled members of the community in core areas of
life. More focus and energy must be directed towards ensuring that disabled
people
and those who experience chronic conditions receive the clinical care and
treatment they require. Everyone should have access to
high quality resources
and support to enable them to reach their full potential.
- There
are well known and acknowledged limitations and constraints with clinical and
support service provision in relation to many
physical and mental illnesses in
New Zealand. Medications available in other jurisdictions are not available to
New Zealanders. Innovative
and people-centred resources and support models are
either not available at all or are provided only on a limited basis through
small
scale pilot projects.
- These
types of limitations could effectively result in a “Clayton’s
choice” for disabled people, whereby an inability
to access the services,
medication or supports that would improve quality or length of life mean that an
individual might feel that
there is no option but to access assisted dying
procedures. The lower cost and relative ease with which an assisted dying
process
could be accessed, as compared with the difficulties and obstacles (both
practical and financial) of trying to obtain adequate social,
medical and
practical supports for chronic conditions, is a matter of considerable
concern.
- New
Zealand has ratified the Convention on the Rights of People with Disabilities
(the “CRPD”). This obliges the government
to promote, protect and
ensure the full and equal enjoyment of all human rights and fundamental freedoms
by all persons with disabilities,
and to promote respect for their inherent
dignity.
- People
with disabilities include those who have long-term physical, mental,
intellectual or sensory impairments which in interaction
with various barriers
may hinder their full and effective participation in society on an equal basis
with others.
- New
Zealand has a long way to go in order to fully meet the obligations set out in
the CRPD. Our focus should be on ensuring progress
in this area and better
meeting the needs of disabled New Zealanders and those with chronic health
conditions.
Palliative care provisions
- A
core component of the Commission’s 2016 submission was the need to
consider the issue of end of life assistance for the terminally
ill in the
context of palliative care service provision. Ensuring that high quality
palliative care services are (and always remain)
available and accessible for
all New Zealanders is a crucial aspect of ensuring dignity at the end of
life.
- It
is essential for this core health care service to be funded and resourced
appropriately to safeguard against assisted death becoming
a “default
option” because of an absence of humane alternatives for those who are
terminally ill. Any consideration of
legislative change in respect of assisted
dying is premature in the absence of a thorough consideration of palliative care
services
and guarantees regarding continued access to, and provision of, these
services throughout the country.
Specific Drafting Concerns
Definition of
“Competent”
- For
the purposes of this legislation a person is considered “competent”
if he or she “has the ability to understand
a) the nature of assisted
dying; and b) the consequences for him or her of assisted dying” (clause
4(f)).
- This
is a simplistic definition that falls well short of common definitions of
“competency” in both the legal and clinical
sense. Furthermore, the
definition significantly complicates, and potentially undermines, the additional
specialist review process
contained in clause 12. The specialist psychiatrist or
psychologist providing an opinion is only required to decide if the person
is
“competent” as defined above. There is no requirement for the
specialist, or the attending practitioner in the first
instance, to determine
whether the individual experiences a mental health condition or a physical
health condition that may affect
judgement, behaviour or
decision-making.
An individual could experience severe depression or be affected by potentially
transient factors such as fear, despair or loneliness
and still easily be able
to demonstrate that he or she understands the nature of assisted dying and the
consequences and thus meet
the legal threshold.
- The
safeguards around coercion and undue influence are also deficient. These factors
are notoriously difficult to identify, particularly
when subtle. The Bill merely
requires the attending practitioner to “do his or her best to ensure
that the person expresses his or her wish free from pressure from any other
person by- i) talking with
other health practitioners who are in regular contact
with the person and ii) talking with members of the person’s family
approved
by the person.”
- The
requirement to “do his or her best” is wholly unsatisfactory and
open to broad interpretation. Although requiring
the attending practitioner to
talk to other medical practitioners the scope of the obligation is not clear,
nor is it evident whether
the obligation extends to all practitioners involved
in care or whether just one would be sufficient.
- More
concerning is the limiting of enquiries with family members to those
“approved by the person”. Often concerns about
coercion, influence
or psychological control are raised by neighbours, social workers, district
nurses, care providers or extended
family. Those “approved by the
individual” are the group most likely to be the protagonists in situation
where influence
or control is at play. The chance of detecting improper
influence through the process outlined in the Bill seems
minimal.
- In
addition, the limitations outlined above in terms of the nature and focus of the
“specialist review” nullify any potential
protection that this step
could offer. A person could easily meet the “competence” requirement
yet still be subject to
influence or coercion (explicit or indirect). Coercion
and influence can affect the exercise of personal autonomy. Disabled or ill
people could be particularly vulnerable to manipulation of this
nature.
Informed Consent, Information Regarding Options and Choice of
Medication
- Clause
15 does not require the attending medical practitioner to provide any
information regarding the risks or side effects of a
particular medication
and/or choice of administration. Strangely, the clause appears to be focussed
only on the method of administration, rather than the actual
pharmacological options available and the risks or benefits of each, as
applicable to the
individual patients’ circumstances. The information that
must be provided falls well short of the requirements for other medical
procedures as contained in rights 6 and 7 of the Code of Health and Disability
Services Consumers Rights.
- In
terms of the information regarding the options vis a vis the other choices
available, palliative care and ongoing care of individuals
with chronic illness
are specialist medical fields. It is highly unlikely that general practitioners
or other physicians with different
skill sets would have the clinical knowledge
or experience to adequately and properly inform the patient of the full range of
treatment
and pain relief options available, in his or her specific
circumstances, and how these would compare with the relative risks and
benefits
of end of life assistance options. Neither do the provisions recognise the
important, and relevant, information that might
be available from other sources,
such as support groups or those experiencing similar
conditions.
- The
concept of informed consent is based on the principle of autonomy – unless
an individual is in receipt of appropriate information
he or she cannot make
informed autonomous choices about medical procedures, including those that might
be available at the end of
life. The provisions of the current Bill do not
support the provision of information to existing legal standards and do not
support
the exercise of autonomous choice by individuals who may wish to utilise
the end of life process.
- Other
jurisdictions that have enacted choice in dying legislation, such as the US
state of Oregon, have explicitly recognised the
need for genuine informed
consent based on full provision of relevant information about choices, options,
risks and side effects.
The absence of comprehensive safeguards in relation to
these issues in the current Bill is highly concerning.
Requirement for Attending Practitioner to be Present
- The
attending medical practitioner is required to be in the same room or in close
proximity to the person during the administration
of medication and until death
occurs (clause 16(5)-(6)). The practitioner is also required to immediately
remove the medication from
the room and return the medication to the dispensing
pharmacist if the person indicates that he or she does not wish to receive it
when asked by the practitioner (clause 16(3)).
- Presumably
these requirements are intended to safeguard the interests of the person seeking
assistance in dying. Perversely, they
may have the opposite effect. Knowing that
the attending practitioner has come to the person’s home and must remain
there until
death has occurred, or that the practitioner must remove the
medicine immediately if the person indicates a change of heart, might
compel an
individual to proceed despite doubts. The sense of urgency to continue once the
process is so far advanced, and the wish
to avoid further inconvenience due to a
prolonged home visit by a doctor or loss of face due to a last minute change in
heart are
very real.
“Cooling off” period /Practical
Issues
- The
Bill does not appear to provide for a specific “cooling off period”
to prevent hasty or transient requests being actioned.
Although it can be
assumed that the administrative processes set out in the Bill would take some
time to complete, the only specific
time requirement appears to be that
contained in clause 15(4). This requires the attending medical practitioner to
advise the registrar
of the method and time chosen by the person seeking
assistance in dying and to provide the registrar with the prescription at least
48 hours before the chosen time of death.
- If
the registrar is satisfied that the required processes have been complied with,
he or she must co- sign the prescription and provide
it to the attending medical
practitioner. The absence of a specific period to allow reflective consideration
of options and choices
is concerning. This is relevant in the context of both
terminal and non-terminal conditions – both of which are known to give
rise to periods of grief, despair and depression of varying intensity and
duration. Quick or reactive decisions could be made in
times of low mood without
a reasonable opportunity for proper consideration. This is particularly
concerning in the context of non
terminal illness, where a considered period of
reflection and consideration would seem to be even more essential in order to
determine
whether a wish to die is enduring and based on clear grounds, or is
transient and based on a lack of appropriate supports or
resources.
- There
are also some obvious logistical issues arising from the process contemplated in
the Bill. These include the transmitting of
prescriptions for lethal substances
in a secure manner, establishing a process for dispensing pharmacists to check
the veracity of
a signature by a registrar, and ensuring that legal requirements
under the Medicines Act 1981, Medicines Regulations 1984 and the
controlled
drugs provisions of the Misuse of Drugs Act 1975 are complied with throughout
all steps of the process.
- Similarly,
the processes for obtaining/dispensing/possessing the medication once a
prescription is prepared in the required form,
seem incomplete and in many
respects incompatible with existing legal requirements around use and possession
of controlled medications.
Nor are issues of approval of medicines suitable for
use in the contemplated manner and availability and supply via Pharmac
addressed.
SCENZ Group and Other Oversight Safeguards
- The
SCENZ group would be made up of medical practitioners appointed by the
Director-General of Health. Functions of the SCENZ group
include advising (in
relation to the administration of medication under clause 16) on required
medical and legal procedures cl 19(2)(g(ii))
and providing practical assistance,
if requested (cl19(2)(g)(iii)).
- It
is difficult to envisage a group of medical practitioners who would be willing
to provide advice on “legal procedures”
and it is unclear what sort
of practical assistance is contemplated, or could be given, by the group. These
provisions are problematic
and open to broad
interpretation.
- The
composition of the group, being medical practitioners only, is also surprising.
There is no provision for an ethicist, pharmacist
or other non-medical
professional. The inclusion of an ethicist in the Review Committee (which
considers cases “after the fact”)
but not in the real-time
accountability structure provided by the SCENZ Group is highly questionable.
Given that the framework is
intended to extend to non-terminal illness the
absence of a person with lived experience of disability and/or long term chronic
illness
is also notable.
- This
focus on a medical model is evident throughout the Bill. This is particularly
concerning given the significant impact this legislation
would have on the
disability community and the very real dichotomy between the medical model of
disability (with disability viewed
as something to be “cured” or
“fixed”) and the social model of disability, which considers how
society responds
or reacts to disabled people. This is played out in a number of
very real ways for disabled people. There are longstanding bio-ethical
issues
that continue to breach peoples’ rights (for example, sterilisation,
access to full information regarding outcomes of
pre-natal screening). There are
also issues of access to healthcare services leading to poorer outcomes for
disabled people. For
example, it is well understood that people with
intellectual disability have significantly poorer health outcomes than the
general
population8, for a range of access
needs.
- It
is also unclear whether this SCENZ group is to act collectively or as
individuals. It is unacceptable to have such a degree of
uncertainty about core
functions and composition for a structure that is intended to fulfil a key
oversight role under the proposed
legislation.
8 Making citizenship and rights real in the lives of
people with intellectual disabilities, IHC, 2017
- In
relation to non-terminal illness, given the potentially broad and imprecise
nature of the conditions that could fall within the
definition, my view is that
nothing short of careful judicial consideration of the specific facts and
circumstances should be sufficient
to enable access to any assisted dying
process. This should entail a full court hearing, with the applicant present,
independent
counsel appointed to assist the Court and expert evidence provided
on key points. This level of oversight and judicial participation
would be
necessary to try and minimise the risk of inappropriate access to the process,
identify potential conflicts and coercion
that could influence the decision and
ensure that any further potential supports and resources are identified. It may
also help protect,
to some degree, against some aspects of the “slippery
slope” that is particularly pernicious for disabled
people.
- However,
I would like to emphasise that my position as Disability Rights Commissioner is
that non- terminal illness should not, under any circumstances, be a
ground for accessing an assisted dying process. The above recommendations in
relation to a judicial process for accessing end
of life assistance for
non-terminal conditions are included for the consideration of the Committee only
for the sake of completeness
in the event that a decision is made to include
non-terminal conditions.
Summary
- As
outlined above, in my role as Disability Commissioner I cannot support this
Bill. There are numerous deficiencies in relation to
the general safeguards and
processes proposed for both terminal and non-terminal conditions. This Bill
proposes a law that poses
real and significant risk to disabled people. It
undermines our place in society and our value as human beings. In relation to
non-terminal
illness, in particular, it approaches the “problem”
from a medical paradigm and does not take account of the views and
experiences
of disabled members of our community.
- Of
particular concern is that this Bill is being considered in isolation from any
discussion about availability and access to palliative
care service provision (
in the context of terminal illness) and does not consider or take into account
the current deficiencies
in support and resources for disabled people. No
discussion about end of life processes can, or should, take place in such a
vacuum.
I oppose this Bill being passed into law.
Appendix A: SUMMARY OF THE DISABILTY RIGHTS
COMMISSIONER’S RECOMMENDATIONS
1 This Bill should not be passed into
law.
2
The process contemplated in the Bill, and the safeguards that are
included, are inadequate in a number of important respects. In
particular:
- the
Bill does not protect the interests of disabled and vulnerable members of the
community
- It
contains insufficient provisions and protections in relation to matters such as
provision of appropriate information before decisions
are made; obtaining
informed consent; assessing capacity; determining if undue influence or coercion
exist; “cooling off”
periods and oversight/approval
mechanisms.
- Legislative
change in relation to end of life choice cannot be considered in isolation from
palliative care service provision and
the current
services
and resources available to those who experience
serious but non-terminal conditions. Disabled New Zealanders are discriminated
against
and marginalised in many areas of life. They do not always have access
to the supports they need to participate in the community
on the same basis as
others. It is premature to discuss law change in this area without considering
the adequacy of existing resources
and services.
- If
the Bill is to be passed in some form ( which I oppose) then the concerns
outlined above must first be appropriately and comprehensively
addressed,
in consultation with the disability community. Further, any access to end of
life assistance should only take place upon
the issuing of an order from the
Court and after a full examination of the facts and circumstances of each
application.
Appendix B:
Human Rights Commission 2016 Submission

Submission to the Health Select Committee in Relation to its
Investigation into End of Life Matters
29 January 2016
NEW ZEALAND HUMAN RIGHTS COMMISSION SUBMISSION TO THE HEALTH
SELECT COMMITTEE IN RELATION TO ITS INVESTIGATION INTO END OF LIFE
MATTERS
Introduction
- The
Human Rights Commission (‘the Commission’) welcomes the opportunity
to provide a submission to the Health Committee
(‘the Committee’) in
relation to its investigation into end of life matters, following its receipt of
the Petition of
Hon. Maryan Street and 8,974 others (‘the
Petition’).
- The
Petition itself follows the landmark High Court case brought by Lecretia
Seales9 which sought to challenge the current legal prohibition
against physician-assisted voluntary euthanasia. The Commission appeared
as an
intervener in those proceedings, pursuant to its functions under the Human
Rights Act 1993.10 Ms
Seales’ case generated
considerable public interest in this issue and has reignited the policy debate
in New Zealand.
- The
Committee has identified four areas that it will consider during its
investigation. The Commission has focused its submission
on the human rights
aspects of areas 3 and 4, these being the current legal situation and
international experiences.
Summary of the Commission’s position
- This
submission represents the agreed collective views of the Commission on matters
where consensus has been reached. The Commission’s
position can be
summarised as follows:
- The
Commission acknowledges the complexity of the issues being considered by the
Committee and the need to balance competing principles
such as the right to
life, respect for human dignity, personal autonomy and the protection of
vulnerable members of society.
- The
Commission is strongly of the view that any legal change that might be
contemplated by Parliament in this area must incorporate
sufficient safeguards
in order to eliminate risk to vulnerable citizens. Minimum safeguards that
should be included are set out later
in this submission.
9 Seales v Attorney-General [2015] NZHC
828
10 Human Rights Act 1993 s 5(2)(a) and 5(2)(j).
- The
Commission considers that a legal framework permitting assistance to be given to
a competent terminally ill adult to end his or
her life (if he or she freely and
autonomously choses to do so), would likely be acceptable if accompanied
by adequate legal and procedural safeguards and in the context of
appropriate palliative care services being available and
accessible.
- The
Commission notes that the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act 1990 (NZBORA) does not
specifically include the core human rights principles
of dignity, personal
autonomy or the liberty and security of the person as free-standing rights. This
stands in contrast with some
overseas jurisdictions. This position is
particularly relevant to consideration of end of life matters but also has
broader application.
The Commission recommends that the Committee consider
whether the current form of the NZBORA adequately engages the human rights
issues that arise from end of life matters.
- The
Commission’s position is set out in more detail below. The Commission
would appreciate the opportunity to speak to its
submission.
The Current Legal Position in New Zealand
- The
current legal position is well established and is noted only briefly in this
submission to establish the basis for the discussion
that follows. Seales v
Attorney General confirmed that any action taken by a physician to assist a
terminally ill person to take his or her own life upon their request constitutes
a serious criminal offence under the Crimes Act
196111.
- The
primary basis for the decision in Seales can be found in section 63 of
the Crimes Act, which provides that no person has the right to consent to the
infliction of death upon
themselves, and that the existence of such consent does
not affect the criminal responsibility of any person who is party to such
an
act. In line with the text and purpose of section 63, and with reference to
similar UK law, Justice Collins concluded that Ms
Seales’ consent would
not provide her doctor with a lawful excuse to administer
“aid-in-dying” to Ms Seales.12
- Lecretia
Seales had sought to test the current position by seeking a declaration that her
doctor would not be liable for culpable
homicide under the Crimes Act if
she
“administered aid in dying” to her; nor aiding and
abetting suicide if she “facilitated
aid in dying”. Alternatively, Ms Seales sought a declaration that the
provisions of the Crimes Act that prohibited her doctor
from administering or
facilitating aid to end her life were inconsistent with her rights under the
NZBORA.
- In
declining to grant the orders sought, Justice Collins held that the implications
of such a change to the law could not appropriately
be effected through the
Court, concluding that “the complex legal, philosophical, moral and
clinical issues raised by Ms Seales’ case could only be addressed by
Parliament
passing legislation to amend the effect of the Crimes
Act”13.
Core Human Rights Principles
- In
his judgment, Justice Collins identified four core principles engaged by
Ms Seales’ case14. They are:
- The
sanctity of life
- Respect
for human dignity
- Respect
for human autonomy;
- Protection
of the vulnerable.
- Each
of these core principles invokes corresponding human rights principles. The
manner in which these core principles apply in the
context of end of life
decisions is a vexed issue and there is an absence of international
consensus.
The sanctity of life
- In
Seales v Attorney General, Justice Collins described the sanctity of life
as “one of society’s most fundamental values”15.
It conceptually underpins the human right to life, itself the most basic
human right16. It is also included in various forms across a wide
range of international human rights instruments, constitutional charters and
bills of rights. Article 6.1 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights [“ICCPR”], to which New Zealand
is a signatory,
states:
13 Seales v Attorney-General [2015] NZHC 828,
paragraph [211]
14 ibid at [62]
“Every human being has the inherent right to life. This right shall
be protected by law. No one shall be arbitrarily deprived
of his
life”
- A
truncated version of the right is incorporated into New Zealand statutory law by
section 8 of the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act
1990, which
states:
“No one shall be deprived of life except on such
grounds as are established
by law and are consistent with the principles of fundamental
justice.”
- Justice
Collins found that the right to life under s 8 of NZBORA was directly engaged by
Ms Seales’ case. In doing so, he noted
that it is well established that
the right to life is not absolute, stating that “....the sanctity of
life underpins s 8. Section 8
does not, however, require all
human life be preserved in all circumstances.”1718
- In
the medico-legal context, this qualification permits physicians to withdraw life
support for patients in extreme vegetative states
without fear of criminal
prosecution for culpable homicide, as confirmed in the landmark 1993 case of
Auckland Area Health Board v Attorney-General19. In that case
Justice Thomas observed that the sanctity of life was “not an absolute
value” for the purposes of section
8 and noted that it could be offset by
values of human dignity and privacy, values “central to our concept of
life.”
This qualification also permits the provision of appropriate levels
of pain relief in accordance with good medical practice even
if
such
doses may hasten death, as long as the primary intention is to relieve pain and
not to end life.
- Overseas
jurisdictions have taken various approaches when interpreting and applying the
right to life in assisted suicide cases. In
the case of Pretty v United
Kingdom, both the UK House of Lords20 and the European Court of
Human Rights21 concluded that the right to life under Article 2 of
the European Convention on Human Rights primarily reflected values pertaining
to
the sanctity of life. Lord Bingham held that the right to life cannot be
interpreted as conferring a right to die or enabling
a person to enlist the aid
of another person in bringing about their
17 [2015] NZHC 828 at [163]
18 Butler and Butler have also noted that the Attorney
General’s report on the 2003 Death with Dignity Bill
suggested that one meaning of “deprive” is to “take without
permission” the right not to be deprived of life
under s 8 or NZBORA
something is discretionary and can be waived by individuals who, for example,
consent to suicide 19 Auckland Area Health Board v
Attorney-General [1993] 1 NZLR 253
20 R v Director of Public Prosecutions ex parte Diane Pretty
&Ors [2001] UKHL 61
death22. The European Court of Human Rights agreed, finding that
the right to life
“cannot be interpreted as involving a negative
aspect”.23
- However,
in its more recent decision in Haas v Switzerland24, the
European Court of Human Rights shifted its interpretative approach and focus
towards an emphasis on personal dignity, and in particular,
personal autonomy.
In Haas, the European Court interpreted Article 8 of the European
Convention on Human Rights, which provides for the right to self-determination
and a private life, as a basis for a right to exercise personal autonomy in end
of life decisions. In doing so, the Court reframed
its interpretation of the
right to life under Article 2 to provide a basis for procedural safeguards that
“establish a procedure capable of ensuring that a decision to end
one’s life does indeed correspond to the free wish of
the individual
concerned.”25
- The
Supreme Court of Canada took a very different approach to the right to life in
its March 2015 decision in Carter v Canada26, finding that the
right to life does not require an “absolute prohibition in assistance in
dying”27. The Supreme Court also considered
that28:
“The right to life is engaged when the law of the state
imposes death or an increased risk of death on a person, either directly
or
indirectly. Here, the prohibition [against physician assisted dying]
deprives some individuals of life, as it has the effect of forcing some
individuals to take their own life prematurely, for fear that
they would be
incapable of doing so when they reached the point where suffering was
intolerable.”
- However,
it is important to emphasise that there is a crucial distinction between the
framing of the right to life under the Canadian
Charter of Rights and the
NZBORA. Section 7 of the Canadian Charter includes the rights to liberty and
security of the person, alongside
the right to life. These concepts are missing
from s 8 of the NZBORA. Protection of the individual’s right to liberty
and personal
security were decisive factors in the Court’s judgment in
Carter.
- Interpretive
guidance about aspects of human rights treaties can also be issued
by
United Nations treaty bodies in the form of “general
comments”. These comments
22 R v Director of Public Prosecutions ex parte
Diane Pretty &Ors [2001] UKHL 61 at [5]
23 Pretty v United Kingdom [2002] ECHR 2346/02 29 April
2002 at [39]
24 Haas v Switzerland [2011] Ap. 31322/07
25 Ibid at [54]
26 Carter v Canada (Attorney General) [2015] SCC 5
27 Ibid at [63]
provide guidance on the interpretation and application of various treaty
provisions. However, to date, the UN Treaty bodies are yet
to develop any
definitive position on the human rights implications of assisted suicide.
- The
United Nations Human Rights Committee (UNHRC) issued a general comment on the
right to life as expressed in Article 6 of the ICCPR
in April 1982. This comment
does not contain specific mention of matters pertaining to end of life matters,
such as physician assisted
suicide, although it notes that the right to life
should be interpreted broadly. The UNHRC is currently preparing an updated
General
Comment on the right to life following its day of discussion on the
right to life at its 114th session in July 201529. Once
available, this updated comment may be relevant to the deliberations of the
Health Committee on this matter.
- However,
after reviewing the Netherlands’ compliance with the ICCPR in 2009, the
UNHRC expressed concern at the “extent
of assisted suicide and
euthanasia” in that country, noting in particular the lack of independent
judicial oversight to guard
against the existence of undue influence or
misapprehension30. The UNHRC recommended that the statute that
legally authorises physician-assisted suicide in the Netherlands31 be
reviewed in light of Article 6 of the ICCPR.
- In
the Commission’s view, the right not to be arbitrarily deprived of life
does not directly translate into an absolute prohibition
on parliament
implementing a legislative framework that would permit terminally ill people to
obtain assistance to end their lives.
This position is subject to the provisos
and safeguards identified later in this submission.
The Right to Dignity
- Human
dignity is a core human rights concept. Human rights themselves have been
described as “fundamental rights which empower human beings to shape
their lives in accordance with liberty, equality and respect for human
dignity”32 and as a “manifestation of human
dignity” that provides the conceptual nucleus from which all
existential human rights derive33.
29 http://www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/CCPR/Pages/GC36-Article6Righttolife.aspx
30 UN Human Rights Committee, Concluding Observations”
Netherlands, CCPR/C/NDL/CO/4, paragraph 7, 25
August 2009
31 The Termination of Life Upon Request and Assisted Suicide
Act
32 Nowak (2003), Introduction to the Human Rights Regime,
Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Leiden p 1
- The
first recital of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights states that the
“recognition of inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable
rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom,
justice
and peace in the world”. The same statement is included in the
preamble of the ICCPR and the preambles of both the ICCPR and International
Covenant
of Economic Social and Cultural Rights (“ICESCR”) recognise
that the rights contained therein “derive from the inherent dignity of
the human being”. Article 3(a) of the Convention on the Rights of
Persons with Disabilities (“CRPD”) provides that the principles of
the
Convention “shall be respect for inherent dignity, individual
autonomy including the freedom to make ones’ own choices, and
independence...”
- In
New Zealand, a free-standing right to dignity is not expressly provided for in
the Bill of Rights and other human rights legislation.
This contrasts with
jurisdictions such as South Africa, where the right to dignity is included in
the South African Bill of Rights,
which states at section 10 that
“Everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have their dignity
protected and respected.”
- The
absence of a justiciable right to dignity in New Zealand law was highlighted by
Justice Collins in Seales v Attorney General,
stating34:
“I fully acknowledge the consequences of the law
against assisting suicide as it currently stands are extremely distressing
for
Ms Seales and that she is suffering because that law does not accommodate her
right to dignity and personal autonomy”
- Despite
the absence of the right to dignity in New Zealand human rights legislation, the
New Zealand courts have affirmed the centrality
of the concept of dignity in
human rights law. In Auckland Area Health Board v Attorney General
Justice Thomas found that loss and degradation of bodily functions invoked
the values of human dignity and personal privacy35. His Honour also
emphasised that “dignity and worth of the human person is a key value
underlying the rights affirmed in the Bill of Rights” in the 2007 case
of Brooker v Police36.
- The
right to dignity has been a central factor across the body of international case
law on assisted suicide. In Carter v Canada, the Supreme Court of Canada
held that the rights to liberty and security of the person are underpinned by
“a concern for the protection of personal autonomy and dignity”
37. The Supreme Court of Canada
34 [2015] NZHC 828 at [192]
35 [1993] 1 NZLR 253 at p 245
36 Brooker v Police [2007] NZSC 30, 3 NZLR 91 at
[177]- [192]
37 Carter v Canada [2015] SCC 5 at [64]
also drew a connection between an individual’s respective senses of
bodily integrity and dignity, observing that an individual’s
response to a
grievous and irremediable medical condition is a matter critical to their
dignity and autonomy.38
- In
the 2015 South African assisted case of Stransham-Ford v Ministry of
Justice39, Justice Fabricius referenced South African legal
authorities that establish the concept of dignity as a justiciable and
enforceable
right intertwined with the right to life40. In that case,
the judge found that a number of conditions suffered by the applicant, who was
in Stage 4 of terminal cancer, compromised
his
dignity41.
- The
observations of the Canadian and South African courts reflect the close
connection between the general concept of personal dignity
and the ability to
maintain control over one’s body and circumstances so as to prevent events
or
insult that the individual might find subjectively offensive. In
this respect, it is a corollary of the right to be treated humanely
and with
respect.
The right to personal autonomy
- Like
the right to dignity, human rights concepts derived from the concept of personal
autonomy have been influential in court decisions
concerning the lawfulness of
physician assisted suicide.
- In
Carter v Canada, the Canadian Supreme Court described the right to
liberty under section 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights as protecting
“ the right to make fundamental choices free from state
interference” and the right to security of the person under that same
section as “encompassing a notion of personal autonomy involving
control over ones bodily integrity free from state interference”,
noting that “it is engaged by state interference with an
individual’s physical or psychological integrity, including any state
action
that causes harm or suffering”.
42
- In
the European jurisdiction, the European Court of Human Rights in Haas v
Switzerland interpreted the right of the individual to self-determination
under Article 8 of the European Convention as creating an inalienable
right to
exercise personal autonomy on end of life decisions.
38 Ibid at [66]
39 Stransham-Ford v Minister of Justice & Ors [2015]
27401/15
40 Ibid at p 14, 16
41 Ibid at p 18
42 Carter v Canada [2015] SCC 5 at [64]
- In
Seales v Attorney General, Justice Collins noted that the concept of
personal
autonomy was “multi-faceted and subject to much
debate” amongst ethicists. His
Honour referred to the concept as encompassing:43
“self-rule that is free from both controlling influence
by others and limitations that prevent [the individual from making]
meaningful
choice[s] [about his or her body.]”
- Justice
Collins noted that the concept of person autonomy was reflected in s 11 of the
NZBORA, which establishes the right of an individual
to refuse to undergo
medical treatment. However, as set out above, he found that New Zealand law does
not accommodate the right of
the individual with a terminal illness to exercise
their right of personal autonomy to end their life with the assistance of a
physician.44
Protection of the Vulnerable
- The
most fundamental public policy impact of any potential change to the law
regarding assisted dying, whether judge-led or through
legislation, is that it
could be regarded as qualifying the State’s protection of the sanctity of
life. Related to this is
a fundamental human rights concern about protecting the
vulnerable from harm and exploitation45.
- In
the present context vulnerable groups may include children, older adults, those
whose decision-making ability may be affected in
some manner, those who may be
susceptible to influence or who are unable to access optimal social or clinical
care.
- This
is an area of particular interest to disabled members of the community for
several reasons. There is concern that external influence
(covert or overt)
and/or internal belief systems shaped by inaccurate perception could lead to
inappropriate access to, or disproportionate
rates of, utilisation of any end of
life assistance if this were legally available.
43 [2015] NZHC 828 at [71], quoting Beauchamp and
Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7TH Ed, Oxford
University Press, New York, 2013, at p 101
44 At [192]
45 For example, in respect of persons with disabilities, Article
12.4 of the CRPD provides: ‘States Parties shall ensure that all
measures that relate to the exercise of legal capacity provide for appropriate
and effective
safeguards to prevent abuse...such safeguards shall ensure that
measures relating to the exercise of legal capacity respect the rights,
will and
preference of the person, are free of conflict of interest, are proportional and
tailored to the person’s circumstances...the
safeguards shall be
proportional to the degree to which such measures affect the persons rights and
interests.”
- There
is social and historical context associated with how society values and treats
disabled people. Community attitudes to people
with a disability and concepts
such as “quality of life” affect the way that disability is
perceived and the way in which
disabled people value themselves and form their
own identity. Fear of becoming disabled, or of becoming a “burden”,
on
family members and others can have an
impact on the decisions
that disabled people might make around end of life choices.
- Such
views may not be based on lived experience or personal knowledge of a particular
disability but on information or attitudes shaped
by the broader community.
These can also be influenced by actual or perceived difficulty accessing
appropriate services and support
that would allow disabled people to participate
equally in the community on the same basis as others. It is likely that these
societal
influences and attitudes, at least in part, may shape the views of some
members of the broader community as to decisions they might
make in future if
they were incapacitated or became ill. Irrespective of any potential change to
end of life options, it is essential
that the community strive to eradicate
stigma and incorrect information about living with a disability or serious long
term illness.
Ensuring appropriate access to services and assistance so that
disabled people are able to participate fully in society on the same
basis as
others will also assist in this regard.
- The
situation is of particular concern in the context of non-terminal but serious
and irreversible illness. The difference between
taking active steps to shorten
life in the face of a terminal illness/ imminent death compared with intervening
to foreshorten life
in a situation where an individual finds their situation
unbearable but is not otherwise facing a shortened lifespan is
complex.
International Policy Positions and Approaches
- A
number of countries have explored both the human rights and broader policy
implications associated with legalisation of physician
assisted dying. In
Australia, the Australian Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission’s
1996 paper Human Rights and Euthanasia considered these human rights
policy implications in detail in its analysis of the Northern Territory Rights
of the Terminally Ill
Act, which (ultimately unsuccessfully) sought to legalise
physician assisted dying in that jurisdiction. The report
concluded46:
46 Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission,
Human Rights and Euthanasia, December 1996, p 18, https://www.humanrights.gov.au/sites/default/files/content/pdf/human_rights/euthanasia.pdf
- The
right to life is a fundamental human right but is not
absolute.
- In
certain prescribed circumstances, there would appear not to be a violation of
the right to life if the law seeking to diminish
the absolute effect of the
right does not involve an arbitrary deprivation of life and legal protections
are in place to ensure this.
- A
legal waiver may be able to operate in certain restricted circumstances if it is
reliable, authentic and subject to appropriate
safeguards.
- In
reaching these conclusions, the Australian Commission ultimately concluded that
political and moral judgments about euthanasia
are not ultimately capable of
resolution through the application of international human rights standards. The
Commission found that
any final political or moral judgment must be made by the
legislature.
- It
is notable that a number of jurisdictions have legalised or decriminalised some
form of assisted dying. For example, Belgium, the
Netherlands and the U.S. state
of Oregon have passed legislation authorising physician assisted dying, albeit
with contrasting approaches
and thresholds. In the cases of Belgium and the
Netherlands, this includes permitting the prescription and administration of
lethal
medication by a physician to both terminal patients and those patients
experiencing intolerable suffering as a result of a serious
incurable illness.
In Oregon, authorisation is limited to the prescription of lethal medication for
self- administration by a terminally
ill adult patient.
- In
Switzerland, the provisions of its 1937 Criminal Code47 do not
prohibit assisted suicide if there is no “selfish motive”.
Accordingly, while there is no specific legislation
authorising physician
assisted dying, this feature of the Swiss criminal law has led to the
establishment of non-profit agencies
such as Dignitas and Exit that provide
assisted suicide services in Switzerland. Legislative change
can
probably be anticipated in jurisdictions such as Canada and
South Africa, where the Courts have held that criminal provisions prohibiting
assistance in dying are inconsistent with relevant constitutional rights.
- The
UK has also considered the implications of legalising physician assisted
suicide. In 1994, the Parliamentary Select Committee
on Medical Ethics examined
issues
47 Article 115, Swiss Penal Code
surrounding withholding life-prolonging treatment, including euthanasia. The
Select Committee recommended that euthanasia remain illegal
in the UK, although
strongly endorsed the right of a competent patient to refuse medical treatment,
positions endorsed by the UK
Government48. More recently, in 2015,
the Assisted Dying Bill, a private members bill which sought to introduce
physician assisted dying for terminal
patients and included judicial oversight
mechanisms for individual cases, was defeated in the House of
Commons49.
Conclusions and recommendations
- The
Commission is of the view that a legal framework permitting assistance to be
given to a competent terminally ill adult to end
his or her life (if he or she
freely and autonomously chose to do so), could potentially be implemented
if:
- It
is developed in a manner consistent with core human rights principles;
and
- Is
accompanied by adequate legal and procedural safeguards to protect vulnerable
members of society; and
- Appropriate
palliative care services are available and remain accessible for
all.
- The
following are matters that the Commission believes require careful consideration
and which would be essential minimum components
of any legal framework that
might be considered. These matters clearly require detailed examination and
further investigation if
any legal change is to be contemplated. These are not
exhaustive and are noted by way of example only.
- Need
for high thresholds. Clear and sensible thresholds are necessary. A minimum
age of 18 and likely death within 12 months would be
essential.
- Decisions
must be free from any indication of coercion or influence and must be
competently made. Systems would be required to ensure that decisions are
competently and freely made. A framework that permits, or requires,
self-administration
of lethal medication may be preferable to one that provides
for administration by a third party medical practitioner.
48 Government Response to the Report of the Select
Committee on Medical Ethics, Presented to Parliament by Command of Her Majesty,
May
1994, Cm 2553
49 http://services.parliament.uk/bills/2015-16/assisteddyingno2.html
- Need
for supporting medical review/and perhaps psychiatric screen. Appropriate
medical evidence must be available to confirm prognosis and to ensure absence of
a treatable/remediable physical or mental
health condition that may impact on
any decision-making ability.
- Cooling
off period. A “cooling off period” would be essential to prevent
hasty and reactive decisions, particularly in the face of recent
diagnosis and
to ensure an enduring and consistent wish to proceed.
- Need
for ongoing monitoring and independent review of the system. Independent
oversight of any system would be essential to prevent abuse or misuse, to ensure
public transparency about what is occurring
and to assist early identification
of any potential problems.
- Judicial
/expert oversight. Judicial level consideration as to whether relevant
prerequisites and thresholds have been met in each particular case would be
desirable and could assist in the identification of irregularities or concerns
not obvious to those directly involved. This input
could be provided through
direct review/inquiry and confirmation that requirements have been met similar
to Protection of Personal
and Property Rights proceedings in the Family
Court.
Alternatively, it could be achieved via a less intrusive
“paper based” review system. Input from independent ethicists
and
others with specialist knowledge or skills in relevant areas (such as those with
lived experience of disability) would also be
highly desirable.
- Participation
by medical professionals and others in the process must be voluntary – ie
an “opt out” conscience
clause. There will be medical
practitioners and pharmacists who would not want to participate in any manner in
the deliberate bringing about
of death even if this were permitted by the law.
Such views ought to be respected and any proposed legal change should contain
“conscientious
objection” provisions similar to the current abortion
legislation. Participation by health professionals should be on a voluntary
basis only and not compelled.
- Cultural
considerations. Cultural considerations need to be taken into account and
reflected in any framework and process that might be developed. This includes
appropriate account being taken of the cultural diversity of the New Zealand
population, including those for whom English is a second
language.
- Need
to ensure access to and standard of palliative care is not compromised and
remains a viable and “first choice” option. It is essential that
high quality palliative care is provided, and remains, accessible to all.
Palliative care is an essential component
of the health system and diligent and
dedicated palliative care providers throughout the country play a key role in
assisting New
Zealanders to die peacefully and with dignity in the vast majority
of cases. Assisted death should not become a “default option”
or a
choice that is made because of an absence of alternatives.
- Importance
of advanced care planning. It is important not to lose sight of advance
directives and other components of advance care planning that can also help give
effect
to autonomous decisions at the end of life, irrespective of any direct
clinical intervention that might be available.
- This
submission does not purport to be an exhaustive or definitive overview of the
human rights components of the matters that the
Committee is inquiring into. The
Commission is cognisant of the complexity of the matters under consideration and
the likely volume
of submissions that the Committee will receive. This document
is only intended to highlight some key points of importance to the
Commission
and the Commission’s agreed overall approach to the issue of assisted
dying. The Commission seeks an opportunity
to meet with Committee to discuss
these matters further.
- In
closing, the Commission would like to note the importance of these issues to all
New Zealanders and the desirability of the matters
being debated in an open,
robust and non-partisan manner.

David Rutherford – Chief Commissioner

Dame Susan Devoy – Race Relations Commissioner

Dr Jackie Blue – Equal Employment Opportunities
Commissioner

Paul Gibson – Disability Rights Commissioner

Karen Johansen – Human Rights Commissioner

Richard Tankersley – Human Rights Commissioner
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/other/NZHRCSub/2018/6.html