Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Technology Sydney Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 8 March 2017
Dephysicalisation and Entitlement: legal and cultural discourses of place as property
1. Introduction
The relationship between environmental degradation and
the discourse of property is profound, yet little understood and seldom
questioned.
Indeed, private property in land and natural resources is
sufficiently fundamental to modern society that market-based approaches
to
environmental regulation are regarded as orthodox components of contemporary
environmental law.[1] But there is
abundant scope for reform. Property is neither a universal nor static concept.
Successful human societies have been
those able to adapt their property system
to changing environmental contexts. The Anglo-American concept of private
property is historically,
culturally and geographically
specific[2] and has been less than
successful at being adaptable to different and changing geographical and
climatic contexts. The question of
this chapter is not whether the basic legal
category of property should or could change to better “address some of the
incentive
systems that generate our environmental
degradation.”[3] The question is
how to do so?
The two constitutive features of the Anglo-American concept of
property are precisely what render it unsuitable as a land use and
ownership
system: dephysicalisation and entitlement. The concept of property works by
excluding or abstracting from the property
equation the physical specificity of
what is owned (dephysicalisation). Consequently, land and natural resources are
regarded as
no more than the ‘thing’ of the property relation.
Abstraction thus makes possible entitlement to property that, untied
from its
physicality and the sustainability of its uses over time, furnish the basis of
its ongoing alienability, and the exclusion
of all others to its benefits or
profits. The conversion, in property law, of particular, unique and
non-replaceable ‘things’
such as land, water and natural resources
into abstract rights over non-specific, fungible and replaceable commodities is
the intellectual
and legal foundation of unsustainable forms of land use. It is
the dephysicalisation of and entitlement to “almost
anything”[4] in the world that
the legal and cultural discourses of property make possible. Further, “the
rewards” that property “promotes
and
encourages”[5] present
insurmountable obstacles to the objectives of environmental law.
Current
developments in international and public environmental and climate law endeavour
to protect both human and non-human biota
from a range of tragedies and
catastrophes caused by unsustainable levels of natural resource use and
consumption. Yet the discourse
of property, which facilitates such use and
consumption, remains unchallenged. The dephysicalisation of, and entitlement to,
the
land and natural resources is antithetical and dangerously obstructive to
the objectives of environmental law. The extension of the
discourse of property
into environmental regulation via environmental markets appears perversely
inappropriate. Environmental law
cannot be effective until lawyers,
policy-makers and scholars acknowledge the ubiquity and potency of property as a
foundational
and facilitative discourse of modern law and society. Property has
played and continues to play a constitutive role in current environmental
crises. To employ the discourse of property in attempting to solve the problems
of its creation is neither rational nor viable.
It is necessary, therefore,
to interrogate the concept of property and its associated vocabulary of
dephysicalisation and entitlement.
Such an inquiry will make possible the
introduction or return of the concepts of locally and physically relevant land
laws within
a discursive structure of responsibilities and place-based
knowledge. Property regimes, or land laws, can only be viable, authoritative
and
enduring where sufficient knowledge and responsiveness to the capacities and
limits of the specific places of jurisdiction are
developed and exercised.
Moreover, it is difficult to imagine how a better relationship between humans
and non-human biota is achievable
without interrogating the very institution
that facilitates the primary dysfunction of that relationship – the
person-thing
model of property law that separates people and
place.[6] According to Sax “it
is those foundational laws that essentially drive behaviour by creating a deep
structure of incentives,
and that fundamentally describe the directions the
society is going.”[7]
Part I
of this chapter presents the discourse of property in legal terms as a discourse
of dephysicalisation and in cultural terms
as a discourse of entitlement. Part
II of the chapter argues that the use of the same discourse of property that has
contributed
to current environmental crises is inappropriate to address those
crises. In its place, the chapter suggests that property, as an
idea and as a
discourse must reflect what it is in reality: the regulation of physical
relations between human communities and particular
places in a finite biosphere.
I Dephysicalisation and Entitlement
‘Dephysicalisation’ describes the gradual
socio-legal process whereby the environment, or more accurately the abstract
‘thing’ (such as land), became excluded from the conventional
Anglo-American property relation, known in the literature
as the
‘person-thing’ model.[8]
Once the ‘thing’ of property had become absent and irrelevant the
‘new’ or modern property relation was regarded
as a relationship
only between persons, rather than persons and things. Hence, the literature
refers to this as the ‘person-person’
model.[9] Owning property does not
signify the ownership of something physical such as land and natural resources.
Owning property signifies
the possession of something abstract, a legal right as
against the legal rights of others. The expression
‘dephysicalisation’
is most often used in relation to late
19th and 20th century property
scholarship[10] but its origins,
which are often overlooked, can be traced back to the marriage of entitlement to
property with the improvement of
land in the writing of 17th century
English philosopher John Locke. What is often missed when focusing on the
jurisprudence of the 19th and 20th centuries is that the
concept of dephysicalised property emerged out of the desire to change land use
and ownership in the 17th and 18th centuries for
particular socio-economic
reasons.[11] Parliamentary enclosure
and the exportation of dephysicalised property, as the dominant paradigm of land
ownership and use across
the world, were part of a pragmatic political and
economic revolution as much as they were part of an intellectual
one.[12] The link between the
geo-historical origins of dephysicalised property and its relevant practice,
industrial-scale food and natural
resource production, explains not simply a
theory-practice nexus but more significantly, its enduring power in contemporary
life.
A discourse of property is fundamentally a rationale of a society’s
land use and resource distribution. It is for this reason
that it is important
to understand environmental crises confronting public and international
law-makers in terms of the discourse
of property that describes and prescribes
the relevant and dominant land use practices.
Environmental awareness and
environmental education have increased during recent decades, yet the legal and
cultural discourses of
place as property have remained intact and are indeed the
key mechanisms of environmental policy and regulation. Why? Because “the
same engines are still generating the same developmental incentives that we had
before the age of what is called modern environmental
law.”[13] The discourse of
property as ‘rights’ or as a ‘bundle of sticks’ is
taught and repeated in law schools and
law courts throughout the Anglophone
world including the UK,[14] the
US,[15]
Canada[16] and
Australia.[17] Legal scholars have
described and debated its historical development and significance for well over
a century. The most common theme
in the literature pertains to the hollowness of
modern property law created by the concept of dephysicalised property. Because
property
is thought to be merely a series of competing and fragmented rights as
between persons, scholars have observed that there is little
to distinguish
property law from contractual relations at law generally. In doctrinal terms,
contemporary property is regarded as
being “devoid of
content.”[18] It is neither
surprising nor accidental that this is so. Jeremy Bentham insisted that it was
only once property was dephysicalised,
once the reference to the
‘object’ of the relation, particularly land, was removed, that
society and law would progress.
For Bentham and his contemporaries,
dephysicalising property was desirable because it afforded the protection of
property law to
abstract objects and facilitated their marketability. Since
Bentham’s time, the discourse and law of property has been almost
entirely
absorbed by the vocabulary and conceptual framework of the
market.[19]
As Shepheard and
Martin observed in the previous chapter, one of the greatest challenges facing
contemporary law and society is to
somehow reconcile the increasing private
ownership of dephysicalised rights to the environment with “increasing
expectations
of public good
stewardship.”[20] This is a
difficult, if not impossible, challenge precisely because people are imagined to
be somehow separate from the environment,
rather than part of it. Whether people
are regarded as caring for the land or exploiting it, the notion of their mutual
separateness
remains. The contemporary and dominant discourse of property has
its origins in the conceptual separation of people from place. The
intellectual
and linguistic appellation of almost all non-human biota as the undifferentiated
and collective entity ‘Nature’
or ‘the environment’
highlights this foundational separation. The separation of people and place is
also apparent in
modern human subjectivity, which defines itself not only by its
separateness, even its ontological opposition to its physical
‘environment’,
but also by its superiority to it, as the
“masters and possessors of
nature.”[21] Regarding
everything other than human as a ‘thing’, the language of real
property law deprives ‘things’ of
meanings and values beyond their
utility to the human economy. Nature has become, as Heidegger once complained,
“one vast gasoline
station” for human
exploitation.[22]
Although
anthropocentrism can certainly be said to be a characteristic of the discourse
of property, the idea of ‘things’,
such as land and natural
resources, being available to human enjoyment does not itself constitute a
culture of entitlement. If the
availability of those lands, waters and resources
were contingent on adaptive and sustainable management, and if ownership were
fundamentally
connected to those management practices then entitlement could not
be said to characterise that property regime. However, as explained
above, the
contemporary discourse of property at the basis of contemporary and dominant
land use practice is not contingent on a
relationship, sustainable or otherwise,
to the limits and capacities of the physical world. And because the discourse of
property
excludes the physical realm the fact of human agency in the landscape
through land use practices is erased. ‘Nature’
is simply regarded as
a resource, and property relations, so far as they have anything to do with
‘things’, consist only
in the entitlement to those things.
The
ideas of ‘nature’ and ‘the environment’ as being
separate and subordinate to human subjectivity are made
real by cultural and
economic practices including especially land use and natural resource
management. The discourse of property
as rights and the theory of
dephysicalisation are nowhere more apparent than in the landscape itself. The
irrelevance of place, its
lack of uniqueness, distinctiveness and particularity
to human society is tangibly evident on industrial farms and pastures and in
the
degradation of the atmosphere and hydrosphere. Precisely because the discourse
of property is a discourse of abstract rights
as between persons, the limits and
capacities of the physical world are irrelevant to, and excluded from, the
concept of ownership.
Ownership is not about responsibilities to and management
of place. Ownership is about entitlement to ‘things’ and
‘resources’.[23]
Landholders or proprietors of large tracts of land including farmers,
pastoralists and irrigators sometimes identify themselves as
‘battlers’ or ‘pioneers’ and often describe their
relationship to land as one of immense hardship and enduring
courage.[24] The land is
‘battled’ to release its marketable goods. Their ownership of land
and water depends on their ability to
subdue and appropriate the physical world
for its value as a commodity. Perhaps it is in part due to the difficulties
experienced
by human societies endeavouring to impose foreign and often
maladapted land use practices in ‘new’ lands and on
‘frontiers’
that when the land does ‘yield’ its produce
those societies perceive the produce as ‘things’ to which they
are
entitled. The historical development of property law in former British colonies
encouraged and facilitated those land use practices
through initiatives such as
pastoral leases.[25] As Sax argued:
“the existing property system incentivises the manipulation of land and
water to produce those things that promote
the displacement of natural services
in favour of various kinds of manufactured
services.”[26]
Entitlement
to ‘nature’ and ‘the environment’ is also evident in
disputes over land and natural resources
that the law categorises and treats as
disputes over rights between persons or legal entities. The resolution of the
dispute is reached
not by assessing and evaluating competing forms of more or
less appropriate land use practices but by comparing legal rights that
exist
independently of those practices. The culture of entitlement is evident
especially in compulsory acquisition and ‘takings’
case law. In such
a setting “[t]here is almost no notion of use entitlements that are
withheld because of some interest of
the public; nor is there any affirmative
obligation to use one’s property in a way that is beneficial to the
public.”[27] The notion of
compensation is therefore central to the idea that persons or entities are
entitled by virtue of their property right
to a monetary substitute for land,
waters and natural resources. In the Australian case of
Newcrest[28] for
example, the argument that the property rights of a mining corporation would be
sterilised not by the compulsory acquisition of
its property but by legislation
relating to the recovery of minerals indicated that the concept of property was
utterly dephysicalised.
In that case, the Crown granted mining leases over
certain land in the Northern Territory of Australia which subsequently became
the Kakadu National Park. The National Parks and Wildlife Act 1975 (Cth)
prohibited mining. The lessees argued that the Government had, if not legally,
then effectively acquired the leases, and that
accordingly compensation was
payable under provisions in the Australian Constitution. Their claim was that
although the leasehold property rights remained, the purpose of those rights was
defeated and thus ‘sterilised’.
The idea of sterilising property in
this case related not to the physical sterilisation of the land by mining the
land but to the
abstract sterilisation or destruction of the monetary value of
the property right as a commodity. The case demonstrates the prevalence
of an
understanding of ‘nature’ as something inherently fungible and
therefore capable of monetary substitution rather
than as something inherently
irreplaceable and unique. The mining corporation was successful in claiming
entitlement to compensation
because what was lost, whilst not the property right
itself, was its value as a commodity.
Another way in which the culture of
entitlement to ‘nature’ is evident is in the language used when
human society encounters
events and problems such as atmospheric pollution,
drought, floods, salination, soil erosion and loss of biodiversity. These are
commonly understood and referred to as ‘disasters’,
‘externalities’ and ‘environmental issues’,
an
understanding which positions those situations outside both the human economy
and human subjectivity. The idea of an ‘externality’
in economic
terms pretends that there is a disconnection between production, consumption and
waste which disavows the human agency
in the creation of that
‘externality’. Malloy asks: “[w]hy are these effects framed as
external or foreign to the
activity of the factory? Why aren’t the
third-party consequences of a manufacturing process considered to be internal
effects
of the profit-seeking venture within the factory? How might this framing
change our thinking?”[29] The
language used to describe people-place relations when ‘nature’
produces benefits to human society is that of ownership.
By contrast, the
language used to describe people-place relations when ‘nature’ is
damaged or depleted is that of victimhood.
This dualism reflects a culture of
entitlement in which benefits are regarded as anthropogenic but damages are not.
Accordingly,
ownership attaches only to benefits. State compensation and support
programs for land owners encountering ‘environmental problems,’
for
example, intellectually and politically separate the fact of land ownership from
the condition of the land
itself.[30] These programs indicate
that, in addition to the entitlement to certain land use practices and to the
profits of those practices,
land owners are entitled also to the profits of
practices that were not physically possible. In other words, entitlement to
‘nature’
exceeds the real limits of ‘nature’ or its
anthropogenically altered condition.
Environmental regulations that temper
property rights are swiftly regarded as ‘interference’ with
necessary structures
and institutions of political order and economic prosperity
including civil liberties and human rights. The defence of property rights
is
strongest in the US[31] but powerful
lobby groups in the UK[32], Canada
and Australia[33] deploy the same
perspectives and strategies to maintain the priority and primacy of the
discourse and culture of entitlement. The
Policy of the National Farmers Union
(US) stated in March 2009 that the Union is opposed to the “acquisition of
productive
farmland through use of the eminent domain process to extend wildlife
habitat.”[34] Any public
interest or private obligation to environmentally beneficial land use and
ownership is simply antithetical to its purpose.
The defence of property rights
is powerful and often successful because the defenders tap into existing
mainstream understandings
and values of people-place relations. In Canada,
although there are attempts to introduce new meanings relating to community and
environment, property rights remain territorial and individual: “property
ownership and rights are part of a person’s
framework for comprehending
their world.”[35] The
discourse of property establishes rules and regulates behaviours that operate at
an almost subconscious level of awareness and
participation. The default
assumption about the ownership of lands and waters is that they are privately
owned. As Canadian property
scholar David Lametti has observed: “[it] is
because private property is so pervasive an institution, especially with respect
to traditional, tangible objects of wealth such as land and houses, that X
respects the duty not to trespass regardless of who owns
the
house.”[36] In the UK the
discourse of property is equally ubiquitous:
Such is the extent to which rights-talk is embedded in our legal, moral and
political culture, it is tempting to assume that the concept
of property depends
for its existence on that of right. Yet the form of modern property, both
legally and in our moral life, is neither
historically nor conceptually
inevitable.[37]
Environmental law
is widely and not incorrectly regarded as a body of public law that has
developed in order to restrain and regulate
the excesses of private property
law.[38] The instrumentalism of
property law has been long understood to be at odds with environmental
protection. Both English and American
scholars observe the tension between the
ideals of people-place relations that form the bases of environmental discourse
and property
discourse. Coyle and Morrow, for instance, note:
Leopold’s observation in his seminal text on conservation, A Sand
County Almanac, though made in relation to the United States in the
mid-twentieth century, is just as apposite in a United Kingdom context:
‘Conservation,’
he said, ‘is getting nowhere because it is
incompatible with our Abrahamic concept of land. We abuse land because we regard
it as a commodity belonging to
us.’[39]
The extent to
which environmental law succeeds in delivering effective regulatory solutions is
thus the extent to which it is capable
of challenging and replacing this
‘Abrahamic concept’ of the environment at the basis of the discourse
of property. Until
it succeeds in reshaping property, international and domestic
environmental law cannot but “float at the surface of our legal
system” rendering the legal system itself “handicapped in doing the
job it needs to do.”[40]
II Against Dephysicalisation – the Need for Place
Sustainability and Environmental Markets
The discourse of
sustainability operates as a corrective to the discourse of property to some
extent in that it identifies the need
for land and natural resource use to be
modified by a longer-term view of providing the benefits of lands and natural
resources to
human society. The Brundtland Commission’s Report, Our
Common Future,[41]
endeavoured to reconcile the twin desires for further economic
development and environmental protection. It suggested that both may be possible
simultaneously. However, apart from the long-term framework, the instrumentalist
view of an undifferentiated ‘nature’
and ‘environment’
of the discourse of sustainability is the same as that of the discourse of
property. Although there
are multiple definitions of sustainability and
sustainable development,[42] each of
which being “necessarily contest and
contestable”[43], there
remains a recurrent theme across the literature notwithstanding the
“weak” and “strong”
emphases.[44] Sustainability is most
often defined and debated in terms of time. However, it fails to consider the
role of property, in particular
the impact of dephysicalisation, on the
environment. The concept of property is questioned only to the extent that the
benefits of
property in land and natural resources are considered too short-term
and exclude the interests of future
generations.[45] It has been argued
that a “sustainable system is one which survives or persists.
Biologically, this means avoiding extinction,
and living to survive and
reproduce.”[46] In more formal
terms, sustainable development is defined as “development that meets the
needs of present generations while
not compromising the ability of future
generations to also meet their
needs.”[47] Similarly, Sagoff
argues that contemporary environmental discourse must eschew the ideal of
conservation and pragmatically embrace
the discourse of sustainability. He
argues that “the appropriate principle is no longer reverence but
sustainability –
the maximisation of human welfare over the very long
run.”[48]
The discourse of
sustainability is limited, however, in its capacity to address the consequences
of the discourse of property and
its culture of entitlement because it does not
question them. The promise of the discourse of sustainability evident
internationally
and domestically is that it advocates the need to be mindful of
the material limits and capacities of the lands and waters in land
use
policy.[49] There is also promise in
the discourse of sustainability in that it re-introduces the idea of
responsibilities[50] in direct
contrast to that of rights which has come to dominate our understanding of
ownership. Furthermore, sustainability raises
the possibility of collective,
rather than individual, interest in land and resource ownership and
use[51] which is an important step
in challenging the individualism that supports the discourse of property.
However, as promising as these
aspects of the discourse of sustainability seem,
it is not a counter-discourse to that of property. Indeed, increasingly
environmental
policies of sustainable development include markets for
‘eco-services’ that are premised on a vocabulary and conceptual
framework that underpin the discourse of dephysicalised and rights-based
property. According to Adams and Jeanrenaud:
Mainstream sustainable development is built on the idea of market-driven
approaches and strategies based on technology and intense
regulation (termed
ecological modernisation). It promises to steer the world towards sustainability
in ways that do not demand too
many dramatic changes, and that do not upset the
comfortable, the rich or the
powerful.[52]
The deployment of
market instruments in environmental law and policy maintains an out-dated and
not entirely persuasive critique[53]
of direct government regulation of environmental and land use problems whereby
regulators are regarded as “having failed the
citizens and squandered
common resources.”[54] The
market however is a creature of the legal and cultural discourses of property in
which land and natural resources are dephysicalised
and where information about
the resource itself is secondary to information about its value to the
marketplace. The extent to which
environmental markets can deliver the
objectives of a suite of environmental laws and policies is prevented by the
fact of its preservation
and augmentation of the logic of property: the
dephysicalisation of, and entitlement to, yet more
‘things’.
Unlike the concept of direct environmental regulation,
“the implementation of this broad policy of marketisation has been strong,
vigourous, pervasive and has enjoyed bipartisan mainstream political
support.”[55] Given the
ideological commitment to, and economic dependence on, economic development
shared by many contemporary Anglo-American
governments,[56] it is unsurprising
that market mechanisms are preferred to policies that would
‘interfere’ with property rights. The
use of environmental markets
demonstrates the enduring attractiveness, power and ubiquity of the discourse of
property. As observed
by Shepheard and Martin in the previous chapter, the
discourse of sustainability and the frequency with which it accompanies the
deployment of environmental markets is arguably political compromise more than
legal and economic reform. The marriage of the discourse
of sustainability and
the mechanism of markets allows the public demand for increased environmental
conservation to co-exist with
the private owners’ demand for a continued
“freedom to exploit.” Shepheard and Martin argue “both local
and
international politics of the environment are now characterised by
simultaneous calls for amoral market efficiency alongside calls
for caring
management. The strangeness of this pairing is largely un-noted in policy
debate.”[57] The use of
markets to address environmental problems also indicates the saturation of legal
discourse with law-and-economics scholarship
and its vocabulary:
“transaction costs, externalities, efficiency, wealth-maximisation,
preference shaping, reasonable investment-backed
expectations, and cost-benefit
analysis.”[58]
The products
and services in environmental markets are both ‘things’ and
processes that human societies use or rely on
as resources for life and
lifestyle. The possibility of commodifying these things and processes depends on
being able to assess their
cost or value in precise terms of a monetary
equivalence. The use of market-based instruments to solve environmental problems
also
depends on being able to confidently state or predict the viable levels of
their use, consumption or absorptive
capacity.[59] Taken to their logical
limits, environmental markets would theoretically be able to price and trade
“the composition of the
atmosphere; amelioration of climate, flood
controls and drinking water supply; waste assimilation; recycling of
nutrients’
generation of soils; pollination of crops; provision of food;
maintenance of species and a vast genetic
library.”[60]
The
attractiveness of environmental markets to governments and policy-makers is
political and economic rather than scientific. First,
environmental markets
outsource the task and the cost of restricting the use of and/or reliance on
natural resources by individuals
and corporations to those individuals and
corporations. Second, by creating and regulating these markets, the government
simultaneously
controls and eschews the responsibility for the restriction of
prior (often unarticulated) interests in these products and services.
It is
thought that “[r]egulatory markets may reduce opposition to regulatory
initiatives both by reducing the economic cost
of regulation and by reducing
tension between interest groups fighting over who will bear the regulatory
cost.”[61] The resistance of
resource users to the restriction of their use would be otherwise viewed as an
interference with their property
rights and business interests whereas the use
of environmental markets encourages the users to perceive and experience the
restriction
as a matter of choice. Fundamentally, this approach to environmental
regulation disavows that it is regulation. These “Regulatory
markets
represent command-and-control regulation made more
consumer-friendly.”[62]
Advocates
for environmental markets argue that “[s]ecure property rights provide
both powerful incentives for the preservation
of natural resources and effective
tools to resolve differences over resource
use.”[63] In other words, the
idea is that people would relate better to place if “we attached market
prices to the products and services
it
provides.”[64] The idea of the
market here presumes “that there is a relative or close equivalence
between the pursuit of self-interest and
the promotion of public
interest.”[65] The theory of
market behaviour is imported into the discourse of sustainability as manifest in
environmental markets. Accordingly,
“[p]roperty holders are understood to
avoid bad management decisions because their wealth in the property will depend
on it.”[66] Theories of market
behaviour conventionally suppose that markets are democratic and rational.
Specifically, theories of market behaviour
attribute to market players
rationality that is objective; self-interested rather than in the community
interest; grounded in relevant,
current, accurate and high-level information;
and, that market players enjoy equal purchasing opportunity shared with other
market
players.[67] Significantly,
market behaviour is related only arbitrarily to environmentally sustainable
development – it has not been adopted
as a policy mechanism on account of
the intrinsically environmentally helpful behaviours of market players.
The
valuation or pricing methodologies of environmental markets also operate on the
basis of a series of assumptions about the possibilities
of valuation itself.
First, they assume that value can be attributed to anything including processes,
such as complex natural water
recycling and filtration in the hydrological
cycle, and including intangible aspects of ‘nature’ and ‘the
environment’,
such as aesthetic and spiritual values. Contingent valuation
methodology approaches environmental products and processes, not from
their
economic cost, but from their social attractiveness. Contingent valuation
endeavours to price ‘nature’ based on
what people would be willing
to pay for its products or
outcomes.[68] Hedonic valuation
methodology assesses the cost of replacing or fixing the loss of a particular
product or service by atomising its
integrity as a whole product or service into
its ‘constituent parts’. But both “hedonic and contingent
valuation
methods raise normative questions with respect to the ability and
desirability of quantifying certain values. They imply a desire
to commodify
everything when perhaps there are some resources or certain relationships that
should not be
commodified.”[69]
The
expansion of the discourse of property into the discourse of environmental
regulation, through the institutionalisation of environmental
markets is
inappropriate to address ‘environmental problems’ for strategic,
normative and intellectual reasons. In strategic
terms there are substantial
problems with market design and implementation such as pricing and predicting
market behaviour. As Sanja
Bogojevic argues in her chapter in this volume,
despite the scant attention paid by legal scholars to the question of market
design,
design is not incidental to the effectiveness of a market but vital to
it. Primary issues in design concern the lack of parity of
environmental
‘products’ and ‘services’ and the absence of discreet
geographies that correspond precisely
to jurisdictional boundaries and market
limits. In this sense:
It is fairly easy to assign property rights to some resources and ecosystems
such as trees or a lake. However, it is much more difficult
to assign property
rights to resources such as migrating fish populations and in particular to many
ecological services such as the
role of biological diversity in running nutrient
cycles and water cycles in a forest. The reason is that these resources and
ecological
services are connected to other ecosystems than the forest, and
thereby transcend several property-rights regimes. There is a major
challenge in
designing institutions and property-rights regimes that are in tune with the
functions of ecosystems and the goods and
services that they
generate.[70]
Another problem
with markets, regulated or otherwise, is that they do not account for the
inadequate and imperfect knowledge and information,
relevant to the product or
service subject to trade, available to market players. Although we live in a
time of sophisticated environmental
science, the sufficiency of that knowledge
is rarely suitable for decision-making in markets where risks are cumulative and
permanent.
The precautionary principle of environmental discourse is
antithetical to theories of market behaviour because the former accepts
the
possibility of incomplete or imperfect information whereas the latter does not.
A further strategic problem with environmental
markets, regulated or otherwise,
is that they are arguably too little, too late – the product or service
has almost always
already been produced or consumed for many years (for example,
carbon) prior to the creation of the market, thus frustrating the
market’s
supposed function. Finally, the rationality of market players cannot be
objectively determined against a universal
standard. Rural communities, for
example, whose use of water is central to their economies and cultural
identities, do not behave
rationally in the eyes of many outside those
communities but their market behaviour may be nonetheless entirely rational and
predictable
viewed against internal community standards. Malloy notes that
“[r]ationality is a behavioural and interpretive concept. As
such, it may
vary with cultural
context.”[71] Finally, the
single largest obstacle to the success of environmental markets as a strategy or
mechanism for addressing environmental
problems is that their objective is to
restrict economic choices that the majority of the developed world regard as
rights to which
they are entitled. For instance, “[m]any American
consumers simply want to pay the lowest possible prices for the products
and
services that they demand... For the consumer it’s the best of both
worlds, high levels of consumption without
responsibility.”[72]
In
normative terms, the problem with environmental markets is that they extend
rather than question and modify an already deeply anthropocentric
view of
people-place relations. “The development of specialised markets transforms
the view of nature from a partner to a production
input.”[73] As Marx and
Heidegger complained, the idea that place is separate to people establishes the
possibility of perceiving ‘nature’
as a resource which is in itself
a problem. In Sagoff’s view, in “[b]y ‘putting a price on
it’ we regard
nature as a resource to exploit rather than a heritage and
endowment to maintain. This is the most self-defeating path environmentalists
can take.”[74]
The
intellectual problem with the environmental market approach to environmental
regulation is that its methodologies focus not on
the limits and capacities of
those ‘products and services’ but on the human need and desire for
them. In doing so, the
economic relationship between people and place is
inverted such that the situation of people within place and their dependence on
place is erased. For example, pollution markets are founded on the idea that
the human need for the absorptive capacity of the atmosphere
can and should
prevail over (or be consistent with) the actual and finite absorptive capacity
of the atmosphere. Differentials such
as the particular place and particular
time of polluting emissions are considered irrelevant or insignificant because
“if location
or timing were to matter, trading would have to be
restricted; this would both complicate the system and may reduce the number of
participants in any given trading market below the level required for a
well-functioning market.”[75]
The setting of ‘caps’ on emissions is similarly not determined by
the calculation of the actual limits of the atmosphere
but by the willingness of
human societies to incorporate those limits into their economies. Given that
until recently pollution has
been, economically speaking,
“cost-free”, the debate about pollution markets has most often been
concerned with the ‘new’
costs rather than on the accuracy and
viability of the caps
themselves.[76]
Scholars and
commentators argue that the restriction and regulation of people-place relations
using market mechanisms is “fraught
with corruption as each player has
insisted on having a supersized initial
endowment.”[77] Mark Sagoff
argues that the environmental product or service at the basis of the emissions
market, the atmosphere itself, is too
large to “divide in pieces or sell
in units” so “we either protect (or “buy”) the whole
system or forgo
it; there is no way to trade in marginal
amounts.”[78] This argument
challenges the very structure of dephysicalised property which organises
property interests into fragmented rights
rather than holistic ownership. Legal
scholar Brad Sherman has observed a similar problem with dephysicalised property
and fragmentation
as it pertains to intellectual property in plants and
botanical innovation. He argues that patent law ‘decontextualises’
a
botanical innovation or ‘invention’ from its material conditions to
facilitate the tradability and commercial benefit
of that
invention.[79] The attendant
difficulty with this separation of the property right in the invention from the
physical thing is that it is not biologically
accurate and possible. A more
holistic approach is required, he argues, whereby ‘plant inventions’
are situated within
their “informational and material
environments.”[80] The reason
for this, he contends, is that “the environment is not something that is
simply external to the object. Instead
the environment enters the constitution
of the entity: it is folded into and becomes part of the object in
question.”[81] The holistic
nature of the world, the ‘environment’, becomes lost in its
translation from things with intrinsic values
situated in complex natural
systems into the non-specific objects of property rights. Holistic ownership, by
which I mean a system
of ownership situated within the Earth’s physical
systems of non-fragmented inter-relationships (atmospheric and biological,
for
example) places people not in the centre of a property relation, nor at an
imagined periphery, but as one part of a larger economy/ecology.
Property-in-Place
Against the “intuitive appeal of making
‘things’ the mediator of the (property)
relationship,”[82] the
contemporary and dominant discourse of property in both common law and civil law
jurisdictions excludes from their scope the
physical realm in which they
operate. “In neither conceptualisation is there mention of the specific
features of the resource.”[83]
Using a discourse of dephysicalisation to address, and even solve, a problem
which has physical causes and physical consequences
is neither rational nor
viable. In place of a discourse of property characterised by dephysicalisation,
entitlement and fragmentation,
the law and public policy must develop and
elaborate a discourse of property-in-place which is cognisant of and responsive
to the
real, physical and finite biosphere in which it operates and on which it
depends. Afterall, “[s]ustainability requires that
human social systems
and property-rights regimes are adequately related to the larger ecosystems in
which they are embedded.”[84]
If we accept this critical evaluation of the discourse of dephysicalised
property then the question becomes how to develop a re-physicalised
discourse or
a discourse of property that is situated within place?
First, we must
acknowledge the inadequacies of the current pre-occupation with the outdated and
unhelpful private-public dualism[85]
and the associated hybrid of environmental markets. On the one hand, the track
record of state intervention through public property
or command-and-control
approaches to environmental and natural resource ownership and regulation is
critiqued for its various and
enduring
mistakes.[86] Canadian lawyer,
Elizabeth Brubaker, a staunch defender of private property rights for
environmental protection argues that the public
regulation, approach is
inherently limited by its remoteness from local issues and circumstances as well
as by politicisation:.
Governments of all political stripes have given us thousands of reasons not
to trust them to protect the environment: they’ve
licensed – and
bankrolled – polluters, turned forests into wastelands, emptied oceans of
fish, and dammed rivers that
were once
magnificent.[87]
Counter-arguments
contend that the private property approach (such as environmental markets) to
environmental regulation is equally
and inherently flawed because it is
rights-based, individualistic rather than collective in scope, and ultimately
self-interested.[88] Almost without
exception the scholarship of (or at the very least the argument of) Garrett
Hardin’s Tragedy of the Commons arises in the debate between public
(or common)[89] property and private
property. But this is ultimately unhelpful because in purely historical terms if
nothing else, “there
are a multitude of examples of robust systems and
institutions where resources rights are held by a community” and
“where
those directly involved have successfully managed complex resource
systems over long
periods.”[90] The key question
is not which socio-political structure best supports a sustainable regime and
discourse of property. Rather, the
more important question is how any given
human economy can adapt and thrive, within the limits of its local and physical
conditions
– the regime and discourse of property, if sustainable, would
merely follow from that.
The second step for developing a re-physicalised
discourse of property-in-place would be to acknowledge, draw from and build-on
existing
and often long-standing property systems that take knowledge of local
systems as their foundation. By definition, property regimes
that have existed
for a long period of time are sustainable. The dephysicalised property regime is
young as compared with a range
of property regimes throughout human history. In
fact, “[s]ome of the most sophisticated property rights institutions are
found
in areas in which these systems have developed over a long period of time,
on the order of hundreds of
years.”[91] The reason for
their sophistication is invariably the opportunity that time presents to develop
increasingly in-depth and detailed
knowledge of the limits and capacities of
local environmental conditions. Furthermore, the observation of biophysical
‘things’,
processes and patterns not only within a short timeframe
of several years but over the long term of several generations builds into
a
property regime the necessary flexibility to adapt to those processes and
patterns. “The accumulation and transfer of this
knowledge between
generations has made it possible to be alert to changes and continuously adapt
them in an active way. It has been
a means of
survival.”[92]
Central to
these successful and well-established property regimes is their emphasis on the
local conditions of particular places.
This approach contrasts starkly to the
universalising and universalised approach of dephysicalised property which by
definition cannot
be responsive to local variance and change in physical
conditions. The scholarship of adaptive management is also based on this idea
of
building natural resource use and management systems on high-level knowledge of
specific and changeable local
conditions.[93] Longer-established
property regimes, like the philosophy of adaptive management, use the
specificity of local environments themselves
as models of sustainable systems.
Better understanding of ecological systems and how they function and
maintain themselves can thus yield insights into designing and
managing
sustainable economic systems. For example, in mature ecosystems all waste and
by-products are recycled and used somewhere
in the system or are fully
dissipated. This implies that a characteristic of sustainable economic systems
should be a similar ‘closing
the cycle’ by finding productive uses
for and recycling of currently discarded energy and material, rather than simply
storying
it, diluting it or changing its state, and allowing it to disrupt other
existing ecosystems and economic systems that cannot effectively
use
it.[94] Locally-derived and
longer-established property regimes succeed because the people-place relations
are fully integrated into cultural
institutions including semiotic processes so
that a society or community as a whole is cognisant of that relation rather than
it
being the province of specialists or
experts.[95] David Lametti argues
that the contemporary discourse of dephysicalised property is not only
unsuccessful but unconvincing because
modern property law scholarship
“appear(s) to lack what most people feel intuitively: that property is
about things.”[96] To situate
people within place and to return place to the legal property relation seems not
only intuitive but also necessary for
survival.
[97]
One of the key critiques of
the discourse of dephysicalised property is that it separates rights from
responsibilities, building a
culture of entitlement. The alignment of property
rights with environmental responsibilities into a single, integrated system of
property or people-place relations would form a key step in re-physicalising the
discourse of property. The notion of the guardian
or steward is often discussed
in critiques of private
property.[98] Importantly,
guardianship or stewardship is formulated in the literature not as a rejection
of the notion of right or entitlement
but as something attached to the notion of
responsibility. Hence:
The steward is, in essence, a duty-bearer, rather than a right-holder, but
this should not be taken to suggest that the steward has
no rights. An analogous
concept that captures the relationship between duties and rights in something
like that of the trust....
In a similar way, an abstract account of stewardship
maintains that the holder, or steward, has some control and rights over the
resource, but that control must in the main be exercised for the benefit of
specific others.[99]
Stewardship,
or this vaguely defined duty of care, is regarded as both an ethic and a logic,
capable of correcting existing intellectual,
normative and strategic problems
with the current discourse of
property.[100] “Stewardship
provides a conception of prudent or right behaviour with respect to
environmental harm.”[101]
But as David Lametti points out, stewardship cannot function without first
re-placing the ‘thing’ of property into the
discourse. Including the
physical realm in the model of people-place relations “allows us to
understand a dimension of private
property practice not accounted for in theory:
obligations and duties that may attach to a specific resource. These might
include
an obligation to preserve a valuable resource such as land as a steward,
and even to take active steps to conserve
it.”[102] Jessica Clogg
takes this a step further to argue that stewardship can be adapted for both
individualistic and communitarian models
of property relations because it
includes both place and people in the model. In other words, the
responsibilities extend both to
people and to place notwithstanding political
structures.[103] Shepheard and
Martin argue however, that while the political breadth of the concept of
stewardship provides greater utility at a
discursive level, at the level of
practice those political structures and the tensions between them
persist.[104]
Finally, the
reformulation of the discourse of dephysicalised property into a discourse
capable of describing and prescribing sustainable
people-place relations can
reconnect the cultural attachment to place that was suppressed by, even lost, to
a resource-based view
of ‘nature’. Economist-sociologist pair Susan
Hanna and sociologist Svein Jentoft suggest that the inclusion of
“respect”
into a discourse of property is important. The basis of
respect for ‘the environment’, they argue, is not a lofty sentiment
so much as a rational acknowledgement of the dependence of human society on the
‘things’ of its economy. They say:
In harsh climates, where a respectful relationship between people and their
environment is essential for survival, the oneness between
nature and humans is
emphasised. This oneness reflects a bond with the environment that is based on
dependence. The dependence is
illustrated by the detailed knowledge of plants
and animals held by the Inuit and other northern peoples, as well as by the
ritual
acts used to kill animals by the Bushmen of
Australia.[105]
Environmental
philosopher Mark Sagoff similarly attributes successful property regimes to a
human attachment to their physical environment,
not in economic terms, but in
terms of “affection.” In his view:
If you want to understand what makes the economic use of environmental
resources sustainable – if you want to know how places
survive the
vagaries of the global market – then look to the relationships, cultural
and political, of the people in them.
Look for affection not for efficiency as
the trait with which people treat their
surroundings.[106]
Sagoff
issues an interesting caution to the use of the discourse of property and its
situation of ‘the environment’ as
external to human subjectivity and
economy. He says that scientific discourse, whilst important, feeds into and
from the discourse
of property so that when we speak of the absorptive capacity
of the atmosphere and other planetary ‘support’ systems
we view the
environment “not as a place or even a collection of places; but rather ...
as a sort of global
infrastructure.”[107] The
knowledge of ‘nature’ and ‘the environment’ is very
different to a knowledge of place situated within
that specific place. The
difference is of course that one is fundamentally detached from place whereas
the latter is attached to
and founded on place. Such attachment seems at odds
with the alienability of property and its centrality to the attractiveness of
dephysicalised property as a legal and cultural paradigm. American property
scholar Lee Fennell contended that restrictions or adjustments
to the
alienability of property “can reduce pressure on common pool
resources.”[108] Further,
such restrictions can “complement” and “substitute” for
other, more interventionist measures. The
questions raised about the extent to
which “attachment” to and “affection” for place
translate into its inalienability
are more numerous than can be considered
adequately here. However, it is clear that the alienability and excludability of
property
at the heart of the Anglo-American discourse of property are
fundamental to unsustainable people-place relations. The development
of
place-specific knowledge, “respect”, “attachment” and
“affection” for place has long been
and remains, for many cultures
across the world, the rationale for the inalienability of place that
characterises land laws and land
use practices that have largely proven ,
largely, more sustainable over time.
Conclusion
Regardless of whether we call the legal framework and discourse that regulates sustainable land use and ownership ‘property law’ or ‘environmental law’ or ‘climate law’, the fact remains that viable and sustainable (land) laws exist only when and because they adequately describe and prescribe land use practices that are specific to the capacities and limits of particular lands and waters. The reliance of contemporary international and public environmental law on the outdated and maladapted discourse of dephysicalised property and its culture of entitlement is strategically, intellectually and normatively at odds with the imperative of enduring socio-economic viability. To retain and promote the discourse of dephysicalised property risks the obsolescence not only of that particular paradigm of people-place relations but of the law itself. Law that cannot adequately describe and prescribe viable people-place relations can only ever regulate an imaginary jurisdiction that is not of the earth and its finite systems. The use of the discourse of property in environmental public and international law can change because fundamentally “change in human societies occurs within, is carried through, and affects institutions.”[109] The discourse of dephysicalised property facilitates and protects institutions and practices that are dangerously detached from the physical conditions of their possibility. The augmentation of dephysicalised legal institutions and land use practices invites their collapse and their continued use is fundamentally unsuited to form the basis of a remedy to the problems of their own creation.
[1] Jody Freeman and Charles Kolstad (eds), Moving to Markets in Environmental Regulation (2007) 3, 4.
[2] Nicole Graham, Lawscape: Property, Environment, Law (Routledge, Abingdon, 2011).
[3] Joseph Sax, ‘Environmental Law Forty Years Later: Looking Back and Looking Ahead’ in Michael Jeffrey, Jeremy Firestone, Karen Bubna-Litic (eds), Biodiversity Conservation, Law and Livelihoods (Cambridge University Press, New York 2008) 9.
[4] Ibid 12.
[5] Ibid.
[6] For an analysis of this model see: Graham, above n 2.
[7] Sax, above n 3, 10–11.
[8] See especially John Locke, Two Treatises on Government, (ed Peter Laslett), (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1689); and William Blackstone The Commentaries on the Laws of England, Books 1 & 2, (Dawsons, London 1966) [1765-1766].
[9] For an analysis of this model see: Graham, above n 2.
[10] See especially Kenneth Vandervelde, ‘The New Property of the Nineteenth Century: the Development of the Modern Concept of Property’ (1980) 29 Buffalo Law Review 325.
[11] See Marcel Mazoyer and Lawrence Roudart, A History of World Agriculture from the Neolithic Age to the Current Crisis (translated by James Membrez) (Earthscan, London, 2006) 333.
[12] Graham, above n 2, Chapters 2 and 3.
[13] Sax, above n 3, 11.
[14] Sean Coyle and Karen Morrow, The Philosophical Foundations of Environmental Law: Property, Rights and Nature (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2004) 59.
[15] Jeanne Schroeder, ‘Chix nix Bundle-o-stix: A Feminist Critique of the Disaggregation of Property’ (1994) 93 Michigan Law Review 239.
[16] Crawford Macpherson (ed), Property: Mainstream and Critical Positions (University of Toronto Press, Toronto, 1978); Jessica Clogg, ‘British Columbia at a Crossroads: A Path to Sustainability or the Enclosure of the Commons?’ (2004) 14 Journal of Environmental Law and Practice 189, 192.
[17] Samantha Hepburn, Australian Property Law: Cases, Materials and Analysis (2008).
[18] David Lametti, ‘The Concept of Property: Relations through Objects of Social Wealth’ (2003) 53 University of Toronto Law Journal 325, 339.
[19] Robin Paul Malloy, Law in a Market Context (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2004) 3.
[20] INSERT page reference to Shepheard and Martin here.
[21] Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method and the Meditations (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1978).
[22] Heidegger, cited in David Harvey Justice, Nature & the Geography of Difference (Wiley-Blackwell, San Francisco, 2000) 134.
[23] For a critique of this discourse in practice, see, eg, Paul Lachapelle and Stephen McCool, ‘Exploring the Concept of “Ownership” in Natural Resource Planning’ (2005) 18 Society and Natural Resources 279.
[24] See, eg, Rob Linn, Battling the Land: 200 Years of Rural Australia (Allen & Unwin, St Leonards, 1999).
[25] For an analysis of this history see: Graham, above n 2.
[26] Sax, above n 3, 12.
[27] Ibid.
[28] Newcrest Mining (WA) Limited v Commonwealth [1997] HCA 38; (1997) 190 CLR 513.
[29] Malloy, above n 19, 183.
[30] See Linda Courtenay Botterill and Melanie Fisher (eds), Beyond Drought: People, Policy and Perspectives (CSIRO Publishing, Collingwood, 2003).
[31] See, eg, Alfred Olivetti Jr and Jeff Worsham, This Land is Your Land, This Land is My Land: The Property Rights Movement and Regulatory Takings (LFB Scholarly Publishing LLC, New York, 2003).
[32] Coyle and Morrow, above n 14, 10.
[33] See Andrew Macintosh and Richard Denniss, Property Rights and the Environment: Should Farmers have a Right to Compensation? (2004) The Australia Institute: Discussion Paper No.74.
[34] Policy of the National Farmers Union (2009) Article VI (P) ‘Eminent Domain’, Section 10.
[35] Richard Brisbin and Susan Hunter, ‘The Transformation of Canadian Property Rights?’ (2006) 21(1) Canadian Journal of Law and Society 135, 158.
[36] Lametti, above n 18, 345.
[37] Coyle and Morrow, above n 14, 10.
[38] Ibid 4.
[39] Ibid 149.
[40] Sax, above n 3, 10.
[41] World Commission on Environment and Development, Our Common Future (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1987).
[42] Andrew Dobson, ‘Environmental Sustainabilities: An Analysis and a Typology’ (1996) 5(3) Environmental Politics, 401–428, 422–3.
[43] Ibid 402.
[44] For a critical analysis of “weak” and “strong” discourses of sustainability see Dobson, above n 42, 409–411.
[45] See the chapter by Peter Lawrence in this volume, especially on intergenerational equity.
[46] Robert Costanza and Carl Folke, ‘The structure and function of ecological systems in relation to property-rights regimes’ in Susan Hanna, Carl Folke and Karl-Goran Maler (eds), Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and Political Principles of Institutions for the Environment (Island Press, Washington, 1996) 19.
[47] Gerry Bates, Environmental Law in Australia (Lexis Nexis Butterworths, Sydney, 5th ed, 2002) 120.
[48] Mark Sagoff, The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law and the Environment (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2nd ed, 2008) 159.
[49] See, eg, The Club of Rome, Limits to Growth (Universe Books, New York, 1972).
[50] Coyle and Morrow, above n 14, 162.
[51] Ibid 206.
[52] Bill Adams and Sally Jeanrenaud, Transition to Sustainability: Towards a Humane and Diverse World (IUCN, Gland, Switzerland, 2008) 12.
[53] See the chapter by Lee Godden in this volume.
[54] Sanja Bogojevic, ‘Ending the Honeymoon: Deconstructing Emissions Trading Discourses’ (2009) 21(3) Environmental Law Journal 443, 459.
[55] Stephen Dovers, ‘Institutions for Sustainability’ (2001) 7 Tela, 18.
[56] See Samuel Alexander Kirk Property Beyond Growth Unpublished PhD Thesis, University of Melbourne, 2011.
[57] INSERT page reference to Shepheard and Martin chapter here.
[58] Malloy, above n 19, 3.
[59] See, eg, John Sargent, ‘The Economics of Energy and the Environment: The Potential Role of Market-based Instruments’ (2002) 28 Canada-United States Law Journal 499, 502.
[60] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 17.
[61] Barton Thompson Jr, ‘Markets for Nature’ (2001) William and Mary Environmental Law and Policy Review 261, 262.
[62] Sagoff, above n 48, 90.
[63] Elizabeth Brubaker, ‘Property Rights: The Key to Environmental Protection’ (2007) May Fraser Forum 19.
[64] Sagoff, above n 48, 87.
[65] Malloy, above n 19, 27.
[66] Bogojevic, above n 54, 458.
[67] Malloy, above n 19, 27.
[68] Ibid 167.
[69] Ibid.
[70] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 26.
[71] Malloy, above n 19, 146.
[72] Ibid 182.
[73] Susan Hanna and Svein Jentoft in Susan Hanna, Carl Folke and Karl-Goran Maler (eds), Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and Political Principles of Institutions for the Environment (Island Press, Washington, 1996) 37.
[74] Sagoff, above n 48, 89.
[75] Sargent, above n 59, 504.
[76] Ibid 505.
[77] Sagoff, above n 48, 90.
[78] Ibid 88.
[79] Brad Sherman, ‘Taxonomic Property’ (2008) 67(3) Cambridge Law Journal 560, 565.
[80] Ibid.
[81] Ibid.
[82] Lametti, above n 18, 354.
[83] Ibid 337.
[84] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 30.
[85] As discussed by Sanja Bogojevic in her chapters in this volume.
[86] For an analysis of this critique see Bogojevic, above n 54.
[87] Elizabeth Brubaker, Property Rights in the Defence of Nature (Earthscan, London, 1995) 19.
[88] William Lucy and Catherine Mitchell, ‘Replacing Private Property: The Case for Stewardship’ (1996) 55(3) Cambridge Law Journal 566.
[89] The two are often erroneously conflated.
[90] Elinor Ostrom discussed in Clogg, above n 16, 191.
[91] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 27.
[92] Ibid 28.
[93] See, eg, Allan Savory with Judy Butterfield, Holistic Management: A New Framework for Decision Making (Island Press, Washington, 2nd ed, 1999).
[94] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 21.
[95] Ibid 27.
[96] Lametti, above n 18, 378.
[97] Costanza and Folke, above n 46, 21.
[98] See, eg, the chapters of Peter Lawrence, and Mark Shepheard and Paul Martin in this volume.
[99] Lucy and Mitchell, above n 88, 584.
[100] See, eg, Peter Brown, ‘Toward an Economics of Stewardship: The Case of Climate’ (1998) 26 Ecological Economics 11.
[101] Shepheard and Martin, above n 57.
[102] Lametti, above n 18, 354.
[103] Clogg, above n 16, 192.
[104] Shepheard and Martin, above n 57.
[105] Hanna and Jentoft, above n 73, 37.
[106] Sagoff, above n 48, 165.
[107] Ibid 163.
[108] Lee Ann Fennell, ‘Adjusting Alienability’ [2009] HarvLawRw 53; (2009) 122 Harvard Law Review 1403, 1406–1407.
[109] Dovers, above n 55, 3.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UTSLRS/2012/9.html