Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Queensland Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 10 March 2009
THE UNIVERSITY OF QUEENSLAND
LEGAL RESEARCH SERIES
CULTURAL DIVERSITY AND LIBERAL SOCIETY – A CASE FOR REPRIVATISING CULTURE[*]
Suri Ratnapala, Professor of Public Law, T C Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland; Fellow of the International Centre for Economic Research, Turin, Italy[&]
ABSTRACT
Cultural diversity is a fact of political life. How would
a Nozickian society with an ultra-minimal state cope with cultural tensions
that
arise from illiberal norms of cultural communities, victimisation of minorities
within minorities, claims for state help in
cultural preservation, separatism
and immigration? A society that gives pre-eminence to individual freedom of
choice has no interest
in promoting or preserving culture but relies on
fundamental laws of just conduct and the free exchange of goods, labour and
ideas
to resolve cultural conflict. There is reason to think that such a society
will be more harmonious than one where the state seeks
to manage culture.
AN OVERVIEW
Cultural diversity is an enduring fact of social life. Cultural differences exist within nations and nations share a planet that is home to many different cultures. Even in the most homogenous of countries, where people recognize common ethnicity, speak the same language and largely share one faith, there are subcultures shaped by circumstance such as cast, occupation, wealth and geography. In many countries different ethnic, linguistic and religious communities interact while seeking to retain their group identities. In the history of humankind it is difficult to find a social system that is more tolerant of diversity than liberal society. Religious and ethnic minorities live under the protection of liberal institutions and even groups that bitterly oppose liberalism flourish within liberal democracies while they observe the laws of the land. Yet, not all cultures are compatible with liberalism in the classical sense and the failure to recognize this fact may imperil liberal society. The challenge for liberal society is to maintain the greatest degree of freedom compatible with its own existence. This essay considers the classical liberal responses to certain key questions posed by cultural diversity. It needs to be made clear at the outset, that the term ‘liberal’ is used here in its classical sense and not in the modern North American sense.
Cultural diversity raises five issues for liberal society. The first concerns the extent to which liberal society can or should tolerate illiberal norms and practices of cultural communities within it. How can liberal society protect its institutional framework without self-inflicting similar harm? The second concerns the claims of cultural groups for state aid in the preservation of their cultures. We consider here the politics and philosophy of multiculturalism. The third concerns claims of cultural groups for political self-determination leading to various degrees of devolution of power from federal arrangements to complete separation. This kind of claim is most plausible when an ethnic, linguistic or religious community occupies a historical homeland that has been forcibly absorbed into a larger state. The fourth concerns immigration into liberal societies. Will large scale immigration of persons from culturally different parts of the world weaken the institutions of liberal society? If so what is the appropriate liberal response? The fifth concerns the defence of liberal society against its external enemies. Samuel Huntington’s thesis that in the post cold-war era, the major sources of conflict are not ideological but cultural, though flawed by its attempt to separate culture from ideology, nevertheless highlights the cultural element in the hostility that liberal society evokes. (Huntington, 1996: 28) The last mentioned issue raises a plethora of questions that cannot be given the critical attention they merit within the limits of this essay and hence must be left for another day.
In the following section I explain the sense in which ‘liberal society’ is understood in this essay. The fundamental value of liberal society is identified as the freedom of choice. In the remainder of the essay, I discuss in more depth the appropriate liberal responses to the first four issues raised. This paper is not an attempt to resolve all these issues but is a discussion of the liberal principles relevant to their resolution.
LIBERAL SOCIETY
The liberal society of this inquiry is an ideal type that
does not exist. Most societies that are considered liberal fall well short
of
this ideal. So why base this discussion on the non-existent in preference to the
real? A useful way of improving our condition
is to posit an ideal model and see
how it works in relation to the problems that we wish to address. If it is seen
to work well,
it will provide guidance to action and if it is seen to fail, we
still benefit from knowing why.
There are two ideal types that compete for
our attention. One is the natural order of the anarchist libertarian. In the
natural order,
all assets (including roads, rivers and forests) are privately
owned and individuals freely deal with each other to satisfy their
needs. No
person or authority has coercive power over another and necessary help in the
protection of person and property from violence
is secured by contract. There is
no state and hence no state lands or state welfare. (Hoppe, 2002) Despite its
great value as a description
of the ideal condition of liberty this model must
be rejected not only for the pragmatic reason that very few people live in such
conditions but also because it is inherently unstable except perhaps on a very
small scale. Among larger populations, as Nozick demonstrated,
a minimal state
could arise from anarchy even though no one intended this or tried to bring it
about, by a process which need not
violate anyone’s rights. (Nozick, 1974:
xi) If it could arise, then it will arise in some societies.
The second and
preferred model is that of a society that enlists the protection of a minimal
state. This model is preferred for two
reasons. First, it is closer than
libertarian anarchy to the historical experience of societies that have aspired
to be liberal and
hence we have greater familiarity with it. Second, it
acknowledges the need for coercion to preserve the freedoms that liberal society
represents. As Von Mises observed: ‘The liberal understands quite clearly
that without resort to compulsion, the existence
of society would be endangered
and that behind the rules of conduct whose observance is necessary to assure
peaceful human cooperation
must stand the threat of force if the whole edifice
of society is not to be continually at the mercy of any one of its members ...
This is the function that the liberal doctrine assigns to the state: the
protection of property, liberty, and peace.’ (Von
Mises, [1927] 1985: 37)
In John Locke’s theory, the state is born out of the need for protection
from the insecurity that results
from every man being the judge and enforcer of
his own natural rights. (Locke, [1689] 1960: 368) Individuals escape this state
of
nature by creating a supreme authority under a trust or social contract that
obligates the authority to protect life, liberty and
estate of individuals.
Nozick shows that even without a Lockean social contract, an ultraminimal state
can actually arise through
free contracting for protection services (resulting
in a dominant protective association) and that such an ultraminimal state may
become a minimal state by the acquisition of a de facto monopoly of law
enforcement power and its consequent moral obligations to
offer protection to
non-members within the relevant territory.
The minimal state is the
condition where a dominant protective association has an effective monopoly of
the power to protect its members
from having their natural rights violated by
members and outsiders within a given territory. The minimal state will establish
the
physical infrastructure to perform all these functions – courts,
bailiffs, sheriffs, police force and even defence forces to
protect members from
foreign invasion. There will be no state land other than land acquired lawfully
from members. It has no claim
to un-owned land and cannot gain ownership by
occupation except to the extent required to perform its minimal functions. The
minimal
state will not have the power by its own will to create, extinguish or
modify the rights of its members.
This model requires two further clarifications. The first relates to the natural rights of those who have no capacity to invoke the law for their own protection, such as children. Under a protection contract, the buyers presumably gain protection of their rights and those of their dependents. Would a protective association that is a minimal state have a duty to protect a child against cruel treatment by a parent or other custodian? What would be the basis of such a duty? Nozick does not address the question directly though he argues that children possess rights in relation to parents. (Id: 38-39) A protective association’s obligation to enforce a child’s right against custodial abuse may arise in one of two ways. First, parents may contract on behalf of their children to secure their protection against all including themselves. This is not fanciful as a parent can be expected to secure protection of his or her child in the event of the loss of custody to a separating spouse. Second, assuming that members would be loathe to live in a society that allows cruelty to children, protective associations that offer to protect children’s rights may be preferred over those that do not. The association can give this protection without violating anyone’s rights, for no person has the right to violate the rights of defenceless individuals. It is also a non-redistributive service as we assume that members freely contract for this service. This function will not produce the kind of extensive criminal law that marks the modern (non-minimal) state. The state will be limited to undertaking, on behalf of a limited class of persons who are incapable of understanding their rights or of seeking legal recourse, the prosecution of wrongs known in classical jurisprudence as mala in se. These are self-evidently wrongful acts that harm life, liberty and property. It will not have the power assumed by the modern state to create offences at will (mala prohibita). It is worth noting that the modern state perpetrates its most outrageous assaults on liberty and property by criminalising behaviour that in the natural order of liberty is perfectly lawful. (For an illuminating economic history of criminal law, see Benson, 1990) The minimal state will have no such competence.
The second clarification is dictated by the dynamical nature of society. In
a world in equilibrium, there will be no need for legal
change. The real world
though is one of disequilibrium and evolution. In such a world we will still
expect the basic rights concerning
life, liberty and property to remain
permanent features of liberal society. Indeed it is the persistence of these
rights that enable
us to survive and flourish in this uncertain world. However,
the rules that protect these interests will need on-going adjustment
and
clarification. Herein lies the logic of the common law – the law that
historically has upheld the rights to life, liberty
and property by defining and
adjusting the fundamental rules of conduct to new realities. This is an ongoing
project in a liberal
society. Consider the general rule that parties cannot
withdraw from contracts that are formed by the meeting of the minds (consensus
ad idem). When do minds meet when people transact on the internet? Property
rights may conflict in new ways as a result of new technologies.
New tradable
rights may have to be recognised as resources such as water go from surplus to
scarcity. The minimal state in a liberal
society will be required to develop an
extensive jurisprudence concerning the protection of basic rights. Sometimes the
development
of this jurisprudence may require legislation as when rapid changes
in technology or natural conditions create uncertainties concerning
legitimate
expectations. Hence the minimal state in a liberal society will have in addition
to local courts, an institution resembling
the old High Court of Parliament of
England. This institution was the highest court in the land and (unlike the
present sovereign
parliament) was the ultimate custodian of the rights of the
people. It exercised legislative power only occasionally when ‘the
development of common law rules has failed to keep pace with changes in social
and economical conditions’ or ‘when a
too servile adherence to
precedents has forced those rules into a wrong groove’. (Holdsworth, 1936:
446-447) Legislative power
could not be used to ‘affect the sacred
principles of the common law created by immemorial tradition’. (McIlwain,
1910:
299-300)
THE FUNDAMENTAL VALUE OF
LIBERAL SOCIETY
Autonomy and freedom of choice
The core feature of a liberal society is the maximization of the liberty of all individuals. No person may coercively interfere with another person’s physical integrity or her property or her free dealings with others. A member of a liberal society so conceived has autonomy within the bounds set by the requirement of similar autonomy of others. The essence of autonomy is the freedom of choice. Why is the freedom of choice the basic values of liberal society? Before I answer this question, I must explain why I reject a competing view, recently advanced by Kukathas, that toleration and the freedom of conscience (as opposed to autonomy and choice) are the most basic values of liberal society. (Kukathas, 2003: 39) Freedom of conscience is the freedom to believe. The freedom to believe allows one to believe or not to believe and hence involves the freedom of choice. Without freedom of choice there can be no freedom of belief or conscience. Freedom of conscience cannot be taken away except by mind control, but it is of limited practical value. All persons are free to think but not all have the freedom to act as they think. To be able to act according to one’s conscience one must be free to choose. If there is no choice but to act under the dictate of ruler, elder, church or custom, the freedom of conscience may persist in theory but will be defeated in practice.
That freedom of choice is the irreducible value becomes clear upon steady reflection on the different motivations of human actions. Hume identified interest, affection and principle as the primary motivations for human action. However, it is likely that most actions are driven by a combination of emotions. It is impossible for the external observer to decide which emotion predominates in a given action, particularly when the decision is a hard one. It is easy to be principled, when it suits our self-interest. It is also easy to clothe our self-interest in the language of principle. Even if we can read minds, it is not possible for us to unravel its complexities. Conscience itself is shaped by more basic instincts in ways that we cannot fathom. Hence freedom of conscience is an unreliable basis to serve as the fundamental value of liberal society.
What I have done is show that the freedom of choice is more basic than the freedom of conscience in a hierarchy of liberal values. I must now turn to the question why the freedom of choice is the most important value of a liberal society. The question is answered differently by natural rights liberalism and by consequentialist liberalism within which I include the school of evolutionary epistemology. Natural rights liberals from Locke and Kant to Nozick regard the rights to life liberty and property as held by each individual by virtue of being human. Nozick captures the essence of the natural rights viewpoint when he comments:
Why not hold that some persons have to bear some costs that benefit other
persons more, for the sake of the overall social good? But
there is no social
entity with a good that undergoes some sacrifice for its own good. There are
only individual people, different
individual people, with their own individual
lives. Using one of these people for the benefit of others, uses him and
benefits the
others. Nothing more. What happens is that something is done to him
for the sake of others. Talk of an overall social good covers
this up.
(Intentionally?) To use a person in this way does not sufficiently respect and
take account of the fact that he is a separate
person, that his is the only life
he has’. (Nozick, 1974: 32-33)
The natural rights argument is founded
ultimately on the intuitive grasp of the worth of the individual as individual.
Many consequentialist
liberals who may or may not share this intuition and its
logical implications seek a more testable theory of why the freedom of choice
is
preferable to any system of state regulated freedom. Von Mises explained:
‘We liberals do not assert that God or Nature
meant all men to be free,
because we are not instructed in the designs of God and of Nature, and we avoid,
on principle, drawing
God and Nature into a dispute over mundane questions. What
we maintain is only that a system based on freedom for all workers warrants
the
greatest productivity of human labor and is therefore in the interest of all the
inhabitants of the earth.’ (Von Mises,
[1927] 1985: 22) History has lent
great credence to this theory. The epistemological basis of this theory of
freedom was developed
systematically by the thinkers of the Austrian School of
whom Menger, Von Mises, Hayek and Kirzner are prominent. In a complex world
where knowledge of ‘particular circumstances of time and place’ is
dispersed and subjectively held, it is delusional
to think that the state has
the requisite information to improve the conditions of all by adjusting the
choices of individuals. As
Hayek remarked given their subjective knowledge of
time and place ‘... practically every individual has some advantage over
all others because he possesses unique information of which beneficial use might
be made, but of which use can be made only if the
decisions depending on it are
left to him or are made with his active cooperation’. (Hayek, 1945:
521-522)
Though freedom of choice is fundamental, a liberal society does not secure
absolute freedom. In society, we cannot do as we please
without violating the
freedom of others. My freedom to drive my car on the highway is limited by your
freedom to do likewise. My
freedom to dwell where I wish is limited by my duty
not to trespass on the property of others. The idea of unrestricted freedom in
society is a serious contradiction. A society is the outcome of cooperation
among individuals. Cooperation is founded on the observance
of common rules of
conduct that place restraints on individual freedom. Not only is unrestricted
freedom a contradictory proposition
when used in relation to society, it is
evident that freedom is actually enhanced by restraints embodied in general
rules of just
conduct. (On this question there is no better exposition than that
of F A Hayek in Rules and Order, 1973) These are the abstract
and impersonal
rules that comprise what Hume called the ‘the three fundamental laws
concerning the stability of possession,
translation by consent and the
performance of promises’ (Hume [1748] 1975: 541) They promote freedom by
delimiting the areas
of individual autonomy and by making the conduct of others
more predictable. Every functioning society displays some form of these
rules
for without them, cooperation is impossible. In illiberal society these rules
are weak and are frequently violated, ignored,
suspended and even formally
abrogated by rulers. In liberal society, they are relatively strong and command
a high degree of fidelity
on the part of rulers and citizens.
If the fundamental value of liberal society is the freedom of choice, do members of liberal society have a duty, individually or collectively, to take measures to enhance the choices of others? The answer is categorically negative given the model of liberal society adopted in this discussion. In this model the state has only a law enforcing role and has no legislative power to abrogate or adjust the rights and freedoms of individual members. An individual has a negative duty not to interfere with others’ rights and freedoms and hence their lawful choices but has no positive duty to help them exercise their rights and freedoms or to expand their range of choices. However, we need not take refuge in a definition to justify this liberal position.
The argument for affirmative action typically advanced by American liberals and social democrats is that in a liberal society individuals not only have freedom of choice but also the right to choice. The freedom of choice is distinct from the right to choice. The failure to appreciate this difference accounts for some of the major conceptual errors in liberal theory. In Hohfeldian analysis a right entails a correlative duty on another’s part. (Hohfeld, 1913: 32-33) My right to receive bread is meaningless unless someone else has a duty to give me bread. In contrast, a freedom (liberty) entails only a ‘no-right’ on the part of others that I not exercise it. In practical terms a freedom entails a duty on the part of others not to interfere in my exercise of the freedom. It does not require another to provide me the wherewithal to exercise freedom. If an individual has a right in the Hohfeldian sense to a particular set of choices, then some others must have duties to provide these choices. If that is the case, those who have duties to create choices for others will have to sacrifice some of their own choices and hence freedoms. The argument assumes that society can make net gains in choice through compulsion and redistribution.
The attempt to achieve a net gain of choices through the allocation of rights and duties by some central authority has to be abandoned as an impossible task. No central authority or legislature can command the knowledge of particular facts needed to make the necessary calculations. Not only does such authority lack knowledge of the personal condition and choices of individuals but it also has no way of knowing how its affirmative measures will affect individuals’ choices. Empirical studies bear out the common observation that the extent of state regulation is generally inversely proportioned to the availability of choice in a society. (Miles, Fuelner and O’Grady, 2005) The freer societies have proved far more effective in alleviating poverty than regulated societies. There are also private alternatives to state welfare such as charity and private social security insurance. It is also worth noticing that only free people with property are capable of charity. The state is incapable of charity not only because it is a construct that has no conscience but also because it owns nothing that it has not taken from individuals through taxation or expropriation.
The problem of describing the unit that is considered to be the liberal
society
Society is made up of many associations, both formal and
informal. Individuals are at one and the same time members of many different
associations. These include the family group, ethnic, linguistic or religious
community, caste, profession, workplace, school and
the social club. There are
also societies of societies such as the European Community, the empires of the
past and even the international
community of nations today. A liberal society
tolerates more forms of diversity than any other type of society in the
experience
of the human race. Toleration allows some cultural communities within
liberal society to engage in practices that may seem illiberal.
These practices
are tolerated while they are not based on compulsion that violates the
fundamental laws of the land. A liberal legal
system will punish practices such
as honour killings, forced female genital mutilation and abuse of children when
they come to light.
However, within closed cultural communities, it is not
always easy to detect violations of the law. It may be rightly asked whether
a
society that tolerates illiberal cultural practices may nevertheless be regarded
as a liberal society. The answer depends very
much on whether individual members
have legal and practical means of leaving their illiberal communities. If they
cannot, then it
is best to treat that community as not being part of liberal
society even though it may be located within the geographical boundaries
of the
state in which the liberal society is situated.
The cultural dimension of liberal society
In considering the issues
of cultural diversity as they concern liberal society, it is critical to
appreciate that liberal society
itself is only realisable through the culture of
the people. A liberal society does not exist simply because its principles are
known
through the writings of great thinkers or because they are written down as
law of the land. It exists only where liberal principles
live in the actions and
experience of the people. The fact that the principles are known and are part of
the formal law of the land
is a necessary but not sufficient condition. They
become living principles and living law when the general order of actions in the
community embodies them. Liberal societies, even in the imperfect form that we
experience, are a rare phenomenon in human history.
A liberal society can
disintegrate into anarchy or gravitate to tyranny. The institutional checks and
balances of liberal society
are its own best safeguards. However, this framework
of institutions is built on a liberal culture and not on black letters written
on white paper. Law abidance, toleration, keeping promises, paying debts, taking
responsibility for oneself and enterprise within
the bounds of the rules of just
conduct are the ingredients of a culture that sustains liberal institutions.
This cultural foundation
has been weakened in recent decades leading to what
Fukuyama calls the Great Disruption. (Fukuyama 1999) Though blame for this
decline
is not easy to apportion, Becker (1968, 1981), Murray (1984) and Higgs
(2004), among others, have identified perverse incentives
created by misguided
laws and policies of the welfare state as major causes. Maintaining a liberal
political order is a perpetual
challenge involving the nurture and protection of
the institutions of liberty. Liberal societies need to take hard looks at
themselves
while they look for enemies without.
ILLIBERAL CULTURAL COMMUNITIES WITHIN LIBERAL SOCIETY
Complexity
and division within society
A society is made up of innumerable
interacting groupings or orders. These range from what Hayek termed
taxeis or deliberately created organisations to cosmoi or
spontaneously grown self-ordering systems. There exist between the typical
organisation (such as a corporation or government agency)
and the typical self
-ordered grouping (such as a clan bonded by common culture) many kinds of units
that combine organisational
and spontaneous characteristics such as family,
church, and social association. An individual almost certainly will belong in
more
than one grouping.
In the imperfectly liberal societies of the real world, there exist communities that do not subscribe to all liberal values. This may be the result of historical resistance to liberalisation in a given country as in India where despite increasing liberalisation of the country as a whole, caste status persists in some communities. Or it could be new growth that results from the very freedoms that a liberal society offers. Large scale migration from less liberal societies as well as home grown movements can create these illiberal social enclaves. Even an ideal liberal society that values the freedom of choice above all else has potential to generate associations that are illiberal. Whereas a despotic regime may impose its cultural preferences on the people or seek to ensure cultural homogeneity, a liberal society that gives pre-eminence to individual autonomy cannot ensure that illiberal groups will not form within itself. Religious cults that persuade people to surrender their property and their autonomy to the cult leaders are known to occur in relatively liberal societies such as the United States. In Europe, large scale migration from Islamic countries has produced ethnic communities that do not accept individual autonomy, particularly as they apply to women. How can or should a liberal society deal with such groups?
A liberal society confers freedom to associate and to disassociate. It is hard to think of a community that succeeds in denying this freedom to its members as part of a liberal society although it may have established itself within the physical space occupied by that liberal society. In contrast, persons living in liberal society are free by law to leave a group or association and usually have the means to do so.
The problem of exit costs
A person’s capacity to exit from an
illiberal association depends on the cost of exit. These costs may be minimal as
for example,
if I choose to resign from the University Staff Club. Or, they
could be very high as in defecting from a criminal brotherhood or
a tightly knit
religious community. The question for liberal society is the extent to which the
society may act collectively to reduce
these costs without compromising its own
principles. Kukathas gives a surprising answer. ‘The reply to this
objection, however,
is not to deny that exit can be extremely costly. It is
simply to acknowledge that exit may, indeed be costly; but the individual
may
still be free to decide whether or not to bear the cost. The magnitude of the
cost does not affect the freedom’. (Kukathas
2003:107) This is correct if
freedom is understood in the formal legal sense. The magnitude of the cost
affects the actual exercise
of the freedom. In fact, liberal societies exist
because within them the costs of association and dissociation are relatively
low.
In the imperfectly liberal society I live in, I can join or leave a
political party, change my faith or refuse to join the University
Teachers’ Union with very little cost. If these costs were very high, I
would have great trouble convincing anyone that I live
in a liberal society.
The question is how these costs are lowered in a liberal society.
It is the prevalence of the basic rules of just conduct, namely those that prohibit violence to life liberty and property that reduce exit costs in liberal society. I can leave my associations with little cost because the law of tort, crime and contract protect my freedom to leave. These laws give me a degree of security from personal harm, allow me free movement and communication and protect my possessions with which I may lead an alternative life. Competent and impartial officials and courts help me to gain the protection of the law. An association can persuade me to stay or bribe me to stay, but it cannot use means that are illegal according to fundamental laws of the land. In an illiberal society, by contrast, the costs of exit are very high. Rulers and dominant sections of the society may confine individuals within a regime of control that they cannot avoid or escape. The means by which the regime confines subjects is by the denial of their basic rights under the law. Their personal security and possessions, hence their capacity to lead an alternative life depends on the dictates of rulers. Rulers of these societies typically place themselves above the law and people have no recourse to an impartial and effective court.
Are collective interventions designed to reduce exit costs (beyond enforcing the rules of justice) justified in a liberal society? The thinkers in the American school of liberalism like their European social democratic counterparts consider liberty to be contingent upon the individual’s capacity to form and revise a conception of the good life. (Rawls, 1980: 525-528) Barry argues that in a liberal society, the right of exit must be a real right as opposed to theoretical and hence the cost of exit should not be excessive and contends that the liberal state should intervene when costs are ‘external costs’ meaning costs that may not be legitimately imposed. (Barry, 2001: 149-150) The test of legitimacy is left unclear. Kymlicka states that a precondition of a good life is that ‘we be free to question our beliefs, to examine them in the light of information, examples and arguments that our culture can provide. Individuals must therefore have the conditions necessary to acquire an awareness of different views about the good life, and an ability to examine these views intelligently’. (Kymlicka, 1995: 81) This approach leads to the claim that the liberal society should collectively through mandatory education provide individuals the capacity to form and revise their views of the good life. (ibid; Rawls, 1988: 267-268)
Choice cannot be over emphasized, as it is fundamental even to the freedom of those who uncritically accept received culture. The question is the extent to which liberal society should coerce groups within it to provide the wherewithal for informed choice. Coercive exposure of children to state determined education is unacceptable in liberal society for three reasons. First, it sets up the state as the judge of what is proper education. The state has no such role in the kind of liberal society envisaged in this discussion. Second, it interferes with parental choice on how best to bring up children and hence the autonomy principle of liberalism. Third, it compels individuals to create opportunities for others, thereby potentially affecting their own opportunities and choices.
The idea that the state is a superior judge of a child’s welfare than her parents is a form of paternalism that claims for the state knowledge it does not possess. At any rate, parents do not seem to think so. Judging by parental preference, state education has a poor record against private education. The migration of children from the state to private schools has been increasing in recent times despite the much lower cost of state education. Parents are troubled not only by perceived academic inadequacies of state schools but also by the kind of moral education that state schools provide. While as a liberal I must tolerate freely chosen alternative or experimental lifestyles that are not harmful to others, equally as a liberal I must uphold the right of parents to reject those lifestyles as acceptable moral choices for their children.
The case for state intervention to lower the cost of exit assumes that market forces and information flow of open societies coupled with strong enforcement of the basic negative rules of justice are insufficient to lower these costs over time. This has not been the experience of recent history. The rise of fundamentalist hostility within Islamic communities in the West suggests frustration at the failure of these communities to achieve cultural insulation in open societies.
The problem of externalities
A liberal society is not one of
unbounded freedom, but one where individual autonomy is limited by the negative
rules of justice.
A society of unbounded freedom is a contradiction in terms.
The unlimited freedom of one must come at the expense of the freedom
of others.
The rules of justice, in the sense employed in this essay, are fundamentally
concerned with the externalities that result
from the exercise of freedom by
individuals. They enjoin individuals from conduct harmful to others and require
wrong doers to make
reparation to the persons harmed. The rules of justice allow
me to drive my car but not so I endanger the lives of others. They grant
me the
power to make contracts but oblige me to perform them or pay damages for breach
of their terms.
Sometimes though, persons may cause harm to others by conduct that may not immediately be recognised as contrary to the fundamental rules of justice. Consider the case of a group that refuses on religious grounds to inoculate its members against a deadly communicable disease. The consequences may be catastrophic not only for that group but also for the wider community who do not share that belief. It might seem at first flush that this group is merely exercising their freedom of conscience within the rules of just conduct. Yet, from the standpoint of those who are stricken with the disease as a consequence of the group behaviour, it is a straightforward case of the violation of their rights not to be physically harmed by the wilful or negligent conduct of others. Consider again the following case. If I am traumatized by witnessing cruelty to animals and my neighbour engages in ritual animal sacrifices, we have a serious problem. If these sacrifices cause a general health hazard, the whole neighbourhood has a problem. These are the types of externalities that invite state action and test the limits of toleration in a liberal society.
The common law as an evolving and adaptive system has shown remarkable capacity to internalize externalities by developing rules for apportioning responsibility for harm. The common law tort of nuisance, for example, seeks to uphold the principle of ‘give and take’ and defines the obligations of neighbourliness. (Fleming, 1992: 409) Animal sacrifices in my neighbourhood may be judicially enjoined for causing private nuisance. Individuals who refuse immunisation on grounds of conscience may face actions for damages if they contract and communicate deadly disease. The common law by nature is not proactive but responds mainly to claims made after injury. However, where harm to person or property is imminent from trespass (intentional injury to person, land or goods) or nuisance, the courts have authority to restrain by injunction the harmful activity, particularly when damages will not provide adequate reparation. (Fleming, 1992: 48, 445)
Admittedly, the law does not provide perfect protection. Injunctions can be sought only by those whose rights are under threat from unlawful action and they are not always effective as remedies. It is easier to stop animal sacrifice in public than to compel parents to inoculate children. The liability rules and the remedies developed at common law and equity cannot prevent all externalities and nor should they if the society is to remain liberal. The goal of perfect safety and convenience is abandoned by liberals as unachievable in the real world. The attempt to eliminate all pain must result in the infliction of pain. This insight is an important part of the epistemological case for liberalism.
Protection of minorities within minorities
A liberal society offers
protection to all against harm to life, liberty and property. Wrongs happen in
liberal society but they are
not tolerated or condoned when they offend the
principles of justice. Acts that are regarded as criminal or wrongful by the law
of
the general society may sometimes be culturally accepted or mandated
practices within particular cultural communities. The practice
of suttee
(immolation of widows), genital mutilation of female children, honour killings,
and denial of medical attention on religious
grounds are examples. Should a
liberal society tolerate these practices when they do not produce externalities?
While a liberal society tolerates a great deal of cultural difference, other
concerns are raised when cultural groups engage in practices
that violate the
basic rules of justice that protect life liberty and property. We are talking
here about murder, assault, rape,
detention, theft, robbery, trespass and
related offences. These are indispensable rules of a liberal society that
upholds the freedom
of choice. They are the negative injunctions articulated in
the law of tort and crime. They should be applied in their full force.
Thus,
genital mutilation should be regarded for what it is, namely grievous bodily
harm to which there can be no consent by a child
or woman. They are
indispensable to toleration, to the freedom of conscience and to the freedom of
exit. Admittedly there will be
very serious procedural and evidentiary
difficulties in investigating and prosecuting domestic crime within closed
communities, but
as
Kukathas points out, often enough it is the members of
the community who invoke the protection of the general law. (Kukathas, 2003:
144) This happens because the general law is applied across all communities by
courts and other institutions of justice. Where person
and property are secured,
the institutions of freedom tend to win out in the intercourse of communities.
Where they are not, oppressors
win not just within minority groups but also in
the society at large.
A liberal society can, and to remain liberal must tolerate diversity. Equally as a society in which the freedom of choice of the individual is paramount, it cannot tolerate the denial by the state or by groups of the freedom of individuals to make their own life choices. This freedom is secured by the laws that protect personal safety and by Hume’s ‘three fundamental laws concerning the stability of possession, translation by consent and the performance of promises’. A society based on these laws is a society that allows markets in goods, services and information. A cultural community has a great deal of freedom within these rules to choose their own way of doing things. They may agree to share property and to live by their own religious codes. They may choose to educate their children in special schools or at home. They may display symbols of their faith in dress and in other ways. They may preserve their language and their cultural heritage. However, they may not compel conformity in violation of the fundamental rules of the liberal society.
CULTURAL PRESERVATION – THE POLITICS OF
MULTICULTURALISM
Democracies have witnessed in the last two decades
increasing demands from minority cultural groups for state recognition of their
identities and assistance for the preservation of their cultures. They have
received strong intellectual support from left leaning
liberals. Governments in
liberal democracies make substantial allocations to support the retention of
minority religious practices,
languages, arts and crafts. In some countries
there is growing demand for state provided schooling in minority languages and
in minority
faiths. Kymlicka (1995) who believes that freedom of choice of the
individual is the fundamental principle of a liberal society argues
for state
sponsorship of multiculturalism along these lines on the basis that individual
choices are shaped by culture. In the case
of migrant minorities who have left
their societal cultures to live amidst another culture, Kymlicka argues that
liberal society
should grant what he calls polyethnic rights ‘intended to
help ethnic groups and religious minorities express their cultural
particularity
and pride without hampering their success in the economic and political
institutions of the dominant society’.
(Kymlicka 1995: 31)
There is little doubt that culture has much to do with individual choice. The choices in social life are shaped by both physical and social constraints. Unlike Robinson Crusoe on his lonely island, we find ourselves in society that both inhibits and empowers individuals. Kymlicka argues that a liberal society that values choice has a duty to assist minority groups to retain aspects of their culture. While he is right about the role of culture in the shaping of choice, Kymlicka is in serious error when he infers that the liberal state must therefore preserve particular cultures so that the choices that they generate are not extinguished. I think that this argument misunderstands both culture and liberalism. Cultures, whether dominant or not in a particular geographical space, are forever in flux. They are dynamical systems that respond to information and stimuli. A culture that stands still in a changing world is a dead culture fit for museums. The ways in which culture evolves cannot be predicted with certainty. What is certain is that the adaptive behavior of individuals has much to do with cultural transformation. Cultures that appear to be stable are those that are set in stable environments. Communities that have been spared exposure to other cultures by natural or military barriers may retain ancient ways of life for thousands of years. Such stability, however, is not the result of choice but the lack of choice. In contrast where choice is a feature of social life individuals may embrace new ways of doing things.
State promotion of culture is necessarily redistributive and lies beyond the scope of the minimal state. Apart from this fundamental objection, there are two problems with the argument that if culture is not preserved, individuals are deprived of choices that it offers. The first is that the transformation of a culture may actually increase choices available to individuals. The second is that it involves the assumption that the state knows what choices individuals may wish to preserve in a changing environment. Kymlicka’s argument makes some sense from the communitarian and socialist viewpoints that subordinate individual choice to some notion of collective good. It makes no sense within a theory that gives primacy to individual choice. The retention and growth of culture will depend on free association and intercourse among individuals. Individuals who choose to live in liberal society must accept that their culture will be relentlessly exposed to the free flow of knowledge, ideas and temptations. The reason is that liberal society as explained previously does not and cannot provide protection against exposure to ideas and information without sacrificing its principles. Such protection can be granted only by drastically limiting the freedom of individuals, in particular freedom of communication and association. A liberal society has no interest in destroying diversity but also no interest in preserving it. As Kukathas rightly observes the appropriate liberal attitude to the question of cultural preservation is one of benign neglect.
The ideal liberal society will not have a state religion even if all members confess to one faith. For it must protect the freedom of every member to embrace another faith. Liberal society does not punish apostasy or heresy. It is noteworthy that in liberal democracies with constitutional state-church links the trend has been towards greater toleration and state neutrality in matters of faith. Language raises more complex issues but they too may be straightforwardly resolved. The language or languages in use in a liberal society will be determined by private convenience, not by state command. Since education is privately provided the media of instruction will be determined privately. Linguistic groups who wish to maintain their language may set up their own schools but not with state aid. The minimal state will use such languages as are necessary for the effective performance of its functions. All of this will not prevent a particular language from becoming de facto the principal language through the weight of convenience. Nor will they prevent the emergence of second languages of preference. In this process of selection, some languages will have clear historical advantages such as English in the predominantly Anglo-Saxon nations. This is not necessarily the case. In India there are over 200 languages in use of which 22 are constitutionally designated as official languages. English is not so designated but has become the second most spoken language (after Hindi) and probably the most read and written language. It is by far the preferred medium of communication among different linguistic groups and given its global reach and economic value, is likely to become the dominant language in the country through free use.
LIBERALISM AND NATIONAL MINORITIES
There are few countries in the world that do not have ethnic, religious or linguistic minorities. Countries such as India and Sri Lanka have different religious and ethnic communities who are natives of the land. Some of these communities form nations identified with traditional homelands. In countries such as Australia, New Zealand, the United Kingdom, the United States, Canada and France, there are both national minorities as well as recent immigrants from different societal cultures. Kymlicka argues that in the case of national minorities such as the American Indian tribes, liberalism requires devolution of power ‘to a political unit substantially controlled by the members of the national minority, and substantially corresponding to their historical homeland’. (Kymlicka, 1995: 30)
Liberal society is not an imperial society in the conventional sense though it may be one in the cultural sense. Hence, it has no evangelical mission to liberalise illiberal societies that do not pose any threats to it or to keep within it individuals who wish to quit. In principle, a group within liberal society who decide by consensus to secede and live under different rules should be able to do so, provided that a fair settlement is reached concerning borders and the rights of persons affected are not violated.
National minorities are usually the result of nations and their territories being conquered by or ceded to other nations. The longer these nations are integrated politically and economically with other nations the more complex the solution becomes. A large number of difficult questions arise in reaching a settlement on devolution of political authority to national minorities. The liberal approach to these questions will accord primacy to the principle of choice.
Where national minorities have been politically and economically integrated for long periods, it may not be possible to achieve separation without damaging the liberal character of the society unless the seceding nation is also liberal in its culture and institutions. The reason is that the members of the minority and majority communities may have intermingled geographically and culturally under a liberal regime to the extent that a liberal society may not be able to meet the historical claims of separatists without violating its fundamental commitment to the autonomy of the individual. Individuals who do not wish to leave the liberal society may find themselves within the jurisdiction of the separating entity. In such cases, the terms of separation may have to include adequate compensation to those individuals to enable them to relocate to the liberal society. Where separation is feasible, a number of different models of devolution may be considered by all parties. They range from various kinds of federal arrangements to complete independence. Federal arrangements are useful options not only because they can address the concerns of nations regarding territorial integrity and national security but also because they enhance the freedom of choice of individuals by allowing them free movement and domicile within and among jurisdictions of their choice. Free trade and intercourse that is a feature of functioning federations have proved superior in maintaining liberal society than enforced unity.
THE QUESTION OF MIGRATION: HARD BORDERS, SOFT BORDERS OR NO BORDERS?
Territoriality and state
borders
Migration, settlement and colonisation figure prominently in the
natural history of the human race. Some communities such as those
linked by
faith or language may stretch across territorial, national and ethnic divisions.
All the same, as a general feature, human
communities from the earliest tribes
to the modern nation states have tended to be territorial. In the natural order
of things unoccupied
lands are susceptible to possession and ownership by
successful occupiers. Successful occupation depends on many factors including
the location of the land and possible resistance of neighbours. However, the
world today is territorially divided among states, even
those parts that are
uninhabited such as the Antarctic continent. (See Art IV of the Antarctic
Treaty) Even large parts of the sea are allocated to littoral states by the
creation of exclusive economic zones under the international
law of the sea. The
nation state has successfully established control over all un-owned real
property on the basis of state sovereignty
and even owned real property by right
of eminent domain. So this form of migration by occupation is not possible
without confronting
the force of the state. In nation states, legal immigration
is at the discretion of the state.
There are diverse kinds of borders ranging from the hard external borders of nation states to ultra soft borders that separate states within federations. Borders become soft to the extent that aliens are granted the liberty of entry. The internal borders of the USA are ultra soft as they permit US nationals and residents to migrate freely from state to state with minimal legal constraints. The nations of the European Union have soft borders in respect of EU citizens who have the liberty to seek employment and to reside within any of the member countries. This is not an unlimited freedom as migrants must meet local occupational licensing requirements and clear welfare eligibility hurdles. States typically discriminate in selecting who may enter and on what terms they enter. As an Australian national I have greater licence to visit the United Kingdom and the United States than nationals of many other countries. Most liberal democratic states have facially non-discriminatory immigration laws but they impact differently on persons depending on factors such as skills, capital, language proficiency and family connections. Many countries admit political refugees and asylum seekers either by independent choice or by obligations undertaken under international conventions. What is the liberal attitude to immigration? A useful way to proceed is by imagining the position in the stateless society of the anarchist libertarian followed by an examination of the position in a society subject to the minimal state and the society as currently found under liberal democratic systems.
In the libertarian anarchy, every asset including roads, rivers, forests and coast is privately owned. (Hoppe, 2002: 77; Block, 1998: 173) There is no state, hence no state land and no state welfare. An alien cannot legally enter the territory under these conditions without the agreement of the relevant property owners. In other words an alien does not have the ‘right’ to immigrate to the territory. However, in a free society of property owners each owner must presumptively have the liberty to invite aliens onto their property. A member may wish to invite an alien for economic reasons to secure labour, capital or know-how unavailable within the society. Or, a member may invite an alien for sentimental reasons as in the case of family reunion or for compassionate reasons as in the case of asylum seekers. Block and Hoppe predict that there will be no mass immigration into such a society. Successful immigration will depend on the immigrant securing through contract or private charity, employment, housing, school admission and other necessities of life. It is also possible that under an agreement among property owners, the inviting property owner may not have the right to invite a stranger on to his property without the consent of other property owners. This is what happens typically in private clubs and in theory will happen in a small anarchical-libertarian society.
Consider now a society subject to the minimal state. The hypothetical minimal state is constitutionally limited to the functions of protecting person and property and of enforcing contracts. It owns no property except what is needed for the machinery of law enforcement. It has no power to tax but receives only fees for its service. It has no power to transfer wealth from one to another. The position under such a regime will be exactly the same as in the natural order. An alien may enter on the invitation of a property owner and will be able to remain only through private charity or by purchase of the necessities of life with the wealth he brings or the income he earns by trade or occupation. Under such a regime of personal responsibility, if an immigrant causes damage to another and has no assets to compensate the loss, the inviting member may be liable for the compensation. This rule may result from contract among members. Alternatively, it will be derived from the general principles of vicarious liability for wrongful damage. Mass migration under these conditions is hard to imagine.
The conditions in the real world are very different. The state is not limited to the function of protecting the citizens’ rights. It can tax and spend and transfer wealth in innumerable ways. It holds all land that is not privately owned. Every piece of privately owned land is susceptible to the eminent domain claims of the state. It owns schools and universities which may admit foreign students. It controls the territory in a more profound way. No alien may enter without its consent and it may admit at its pleasure anyone. It can settle immigrants and sustain them with wealth expropriated from citizens. There is no reason for liberals to accept these conditions even though the prospects of the state retreating to its minimal functions are remote in the short term. The case for winding back the state must be consistently made and the critical re-examination of the state’s role in relation to human migration must be form part of this effort.
In a society that gives pre-eminence to freedom of choice, there will not be forced integration or exclusion. The principle of non-integration means that no person is compelled to admit another person on to his property or be forced to provide charity. It also means that the state must not transfer wealth including state lands to facilitate immigration. The principle of non-exclusion means that no person is prevented from admitting an alien to his property or from dealing with an alien except on a legitimate ground such as security or health hazard. The state’s role is to maintain these conditions so that immigration takes place as an exercise of choice by the members of society and their invitees. Walter Block’s view of the libertarian position on immigration is essentially the same. Block argues that ‘the totally free movement of goods, factors of production, money, and, most important of all, people, is part and parcel of this traditional libertarian philosophy ... Like tariffs and exchange controls, migration control of whatever type are egregious violations of laissez faire capitalism’. (Block, 1998: 167-168) However, the implementation of this philosophy does not result in open borders but in clear borders that preserve order under which the freedom of choice is maintained.
It is worth considering the common fears of such a liberal approach to immigration. One fear is that it will lead to the importation of cheap labour that will throw locals out of work or depress their wages. In regulated markets, minimum wage legislation is used as a means of preventing entry. Where wages are unregulated the availability of cheaper labour will result in downward pressure on wages. Importation of cheaper foreign goods produced in low wage countries and the emigration of industries to such countries also have similar effects though not so directly. If it is acceptable to import goods why not labour? Here we encounter the next concern which is cultural – people have greater impact on culture than goods. It is noticeable, that immigration from societies that are culturally similar cause less concern than immigration from culturally dissimilar societies. In economic terms, such concerns arise from the intuitive assessment of transaction costs. There is more trust when people deal with like people. At another level, there is a fear that immigrants inexperienced in the liberal way of life may weaken liberal institutions. Mass migration across open borders will almost certainly threaten these institutions but as speculated herein this is unlikely in a regime of private rights.
The twentieth century provides two interesting historical lab tests on the impact of culture on liberal institutions and vice versa. The first concerns the so-called White Australia policy. For over a hundred years, the state excluded non-white races from the continent, often leading to curious results. The state spurned Indian physicians and mathematicians and Chinese industrialists while welcoming welfare dependent white immigrants. Governments justified the policy on cultural grounds but it was most assiduously supported by the labour unions that feared cheap labour. The policy was officially abandoned in 1973. Since then Australia has admitted immigrants from all parts of the world. The last census taken in 2001 showed that 6.3 per cent of Australian residents were born in Asia, (Pakistan to Japan), the Middle East and Africa. This represents a significant injection of alien culture. Yet, there is no evidence of the feared social disruption. Australia’s record in constitutional government, economic performance and social harmony remains among the best. It is unwise to draw conclusions from one case study but the histories of other successful democracies do not falsify this hypothesis. The Great Disruption in the West evidenced by increasing crime, family breakdown and dependence that Fukuyama describes is more the outcome of misguided welfare policies, the dilution of individual responsibility and weakened law enforcement. (Fukuyama, 2000; Ratnapala, 2003: 17-20) All of this does not mean that immigration from non-liberal cultures in proportions larger than hitherto experienced by western democratic states will not have a serious impact on liberal institution through cultural dilution. The point I make is that migration on a scale that threatens liberal institutions is unlikely to occur under a liberal regime of migration by consent.
The twentieth century also showed that when people have political choice, they tend to choose the liberal way irrespective of their ethnic, linguistic or religious conditioning. The Hindus and Muslims of India, the Buddhists of Japan, South Korea, Thailand and Taiwan, the Muslims of Malaysia and Indonesia, and the Confucians of Hong Kong and Singapore have shown that they will successfully embrace liberalism when given the chance. None of these countries are ideally liberal but they have progressed against severe odds from various forms of authoritarianism and collectivism to liberal political and economic order. This fact must call into serious question the cultural arguments against the position taken in this paper. It is not suggested that that liberal societies have no cultural enemies. The enemies are not all militant Islamists either although at present Islamic terrorism presents the most visible and immediate threat. Wherever a culture is threatened by the freedom of choice, we must expect the resistance of those minorities who believe uncompromisingly that the endangered culture is worth preserving by force. Liberal society being a society of choice and a trading society threatens some cultures by its very existence and for that reason will always have culturally motivated enemies.
Many migrants once they arrive (some even before they arrive) are seduced by the welfare state and blend easily into the culture of dependence, special pleading and distributional politics. In this respect they are hardly indistinguishable from a large segment of the local population. On the positive side, immigrants from societies unspoilt by state welfare tend to bring with them strong family values and work ethics that help replenish moral and social capital seriously depleted in welfare dependent Western societies. Immigrants who are bearers of capital or skills are more likely than not to strengthen the economic and institutional foundations of liberal society and in the slightly longer term so would immigrants who arrive as dependents of culturally assimilated members of liberal society and not as the dependents of the state.
Involuntary migration – the case of refugees
Victims of
natural calamities and human persecution sometimes have no choice but to flee
their homelands for survival. Most countries
(but not the United States) have
undertaken obligations to accept refugees through accession to the Convention
Relating to the Status of Refugees (1951) and the Protocol Relating to
the Status of Refugees (1967). Chapter IV of the Convention imposes on
contracting states obligations to provide refugees specified welfare including
elementary
education, public relief and social security. Although not a party to
the Convention, the United States is one of the great asylums
for refugees. The
Convention and Protocol do not apply to victims of natural disasters but many
liberal democracies have humanitarian
programs to admit them at the discretion
of the state. There is no reason to think that the kind of liberal society that
I have described
will be less humane towards victims of persecution or
catastrophe. There is an inarticulate assumption in the arguments of those
who
mistrust liberty that freedom of choice makes people self-centred and incapable
of compassion. There is no scientific or historical
evidence to suggest that
freedom changes human nature. On the contrary charity is an individual virtue
and the freedom of choice
is a necessary condition of it. It stands to reason
that where the state is the great provider with expropriated wealth, the
capacity
and incentives for private charity are diminished. In a liberal society
where the people are not so dependent we may expect more
private responses to
the needs of fellow beings. (Higgs, 2004: 24-25) My experience in living the
better part of my life in a poor
country with minimal social security leads me
to theorise that the level of private charity in a society is inversely
proportional
to the level of state welfare.
However there will be important differences between state asylum and private asylum. A liberal society that gives pre-eminence to choice will allow its members to invite people provided that they bear the cost of their maintenance and indemnifies other members against harm to their rights that may occur from the conduct of the invitees. Under a liberal regime there will be no distinction between ‘political’ refugees and ‘economic’ refugees. The so-called economic refugees are almost always the victims of bad economic policy. International and domestic law is biased towards persons who suffer harm as a consequence of birth, belief or practice as against those who suffer and even die because of the general failures of command economies. The liberal position defended here does not distinguish between the causes of suffering. It does not matter whether a person is imperilled by state brutality, state incompetence or natural disaster. The decision to help rests with individuals and not with governments or the United Nations agencies. The liberal position is thus more humane than the statist philosophy that currently ordains the international law relating to asylum.
The pro-refugee activists and organisations should welcome the liberal position as it allows them to take direct action. They and other associations currently providing private humanitarian assistance worldwide will have the power to sponsor people to their own countries by bearing the cost of entry, settlement and social security and by indemnifying fellow citizens against harm. A liberal policy will not stand in the way of anyone supporting private refugee programs. The difference is that such programs will be funded not by state taxation as at present but by private donations. Refugee advocacy under current statist conditions amounts to the demand that all members of society be compelled to support refugee settlement through public finance. This is yet another case of taking property from some to fund the choices of others. It is always harder to be generous with one’s own wealth than with the wealth of others.
I have not argued here for a borderless society or even for soft borders. Borders of the kind of liberal society envisaged here are effective borders that preserve property rights and the freedom of choice. They are in this sense, private borders. The state’s role is to be gatekeeper for the people.
CONCLUSION
Cultural diversity is unavoidable in the extended
society. I have sought to derive from an ideal type of a liberal society the
rational
responses to four issues that arise from cultural diversity, namely
those concerning illiberal cultural practice, claims for cultural
preservation,
self-determination and immigration. A liberal society that confers pre-eminence
on the freedom of choice must accept
diversity to the extent that is consistent
with that freedom. Accepting diversity is conceding to others their freedom of
choice
as to how they live. Freedom of choice though is not unlimited, for our
choices are limited by the rights of others. Freedom is enhanced
by subjecting
all choice to the fundamental laws concerning the protection of life, liberty
and property. Hence a liberal society
does not tolerate all forms of culture
but only those that respect its fundamental laws. In liberal society, the
fundamental laws
will apply to all individuals and above all to the state. State
suppression of particular culture is a denial of choice and directly
violates
the fundamental laws. State promotion of particular cultures will involve
redistributions contrary to these laws, hence
must be equally condemned. The
liberal society envisaged here is not a borderless society. It has clear borders
across which individual
members may invite aliens subject to the rights of
others. The fears that such borders will result in culturally and economically
unsustainable levels of migration that will erode the institutional foundations
of liberal society are understandable but unrealistic
within this model. The
ideal liberal society assumed in this discussion does not exist and will never
exist. It is nevertheless a
source of inspiration and of principles for those
who wish to defend and extend liberty in the imperfectly liberal societies in
which
they find themselves.
References
Barry, B. 2001. Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism, Cambridge: Polity.
Becker, G. 1968. ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal Political Economy, 169-217.
Becker, G. 1981. A Treatise on The Family, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Benson, B. 1990. The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy.
Block, W. 1998. ‘A libertarian case for free immigration’, 13:2 Journal of Libertarian Studies 167-186.
Ferguson, A. [1767] 1966. An Essay on the History of Civil Society, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Fleming, J. G. 1992. The Law of Torts, Sydney: The Law Book Company.
Fukuyama, F. 2000. The Great Disruption: Human Nature and the Reconstruction of Social Order, London: Profile.
Hayek, F. A. 1945. ‘Use of knowledge in society’, xxxv:4 The American Economic Review 519-530.
Hayek, F. A. 1982. Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vols. 1-3, London: Routledg & Kegan Paul.
Higgs, R. 2004. Against Leviathan, Oakland: The Independent Institute.
Hohfeld, W.N. 1913-1914, ‘Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning’ 23 Yale Law Journal 16-59.
Holdsworth, Sir W. 1936. History of English Law, Vol. 2, London: Methuen.
Hoppe, H. H. 2002. ‘Natural Order, the State and the Immigration Problem’, 16:1 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 75-97.
Hume, D. [1748] 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Huntington S. 1996. The Clash of Civilization and the Remaking of World Order, New York, NY, Simon and Schuster, 28.
Kukathas, C. 2003. The Liberal Archipelago: A Theory of Diversity and Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kymlicka W. 1992. ‘The rights of minority cultures: A reply to Kukathas’, 20:1 Political Theory, 140-146.
Kymlicka, W. 1995. Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Multicultural Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McIlwain, C. H. 1910. The High Court of Parliament and its Supremacy, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Miles, M, Feulner A J and O’Grady, M A, 2005 Index of Economic Freedom, Washington D C: Heritage Foundation.
Murray, C. 1984. Losing Ground, New York: Basic Books.
Nozick, R. 1974, Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.
Ratnapala, S. 2003. ‘Securing constitutional government: The perpetual challenge, VIII:1 The Independent Review: A Journal of Political Economy 5-26.
Rawls, J. 1980. ‘Kantian constructivism in moral theory’, 77 Journal of Philosophy, 515-572.
Rawls, J. 1988. ‘The priority of rights and the ideas of the good’, 17:4 Philosophy of Public Affairs, 251-276.
Smith, A. [1759] 1976. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Von Mises, L. [1985] 1927. Liberalism:In the Classical Tradition, San Francesco: Cobden Press and Irvington-on-Hudson: NY: The Foundation for Economic Education.
[*] S Ratnapala,
'Cultural Diversity and Liberal Society' (2005) 10 (2) The Independent Review
249-271
Sections of this article are reprinted with permission from
the publisher of The Independent Review: A Journal of Political Economy
(Fall 2005, Volume X, no. 2, pp. 249-271). © Copyright 2005, The
Independent Institute, 100 Swan Way, Oakland, CA 94621-1428
USA; info@independent.org; www.independent.org
† The author gratefully acknowledges the comments of Professor Enrico Colombatto, Director of the International Centre for Economic Research, Turin, Italy, Dr Eamon Butler, Director of the Adam Smith Institute and the anonymous referee. A version of this paper was presented at the 2004 Mont Pelerin Society General Meeting in Salt Lake City Utah, 14-19 August 2004.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UQLRS/2005/3.html