Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Queensland Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 8 January 2009
THE UNIVERSITY OF QUEENSLAND
LEGAL RESEARCH SERIES
This article was originally published in Constitutional Political Economy published by Springer and reproduced here with kind permission.
S Ratnapala, 'Eighteenth-century Evolutionary Thought and Its Relevance in the Age of Legislation' (2001) 12 (1) Constitutional Political Economy 51-75
Eighteenth Century Evolutionary Thought and its Relevance in the Age of Legislation1
SURI RATNAPALA
T C Beirne School of Law, University of
Queensland, Australia, 4072
Abstract. This essay revisits the evolutionist writings of the eighteenth century to clarify their key ideas concerning legal and social evolution and to assess their relevance in the present era of pervasive legislation. The discovery of the principle of the accumulation of design is traced to these writings and the continuity of twentieth century spontaneous order theory and new institutional economics with this tradition is noted. While highlighting the contributions of other institutional theorists to the elucidation of the role of purposive action in legal evolution the author argues that input designing does not alter the fundamental nature of legal emergence as postulated by the eighteenth century scholars. The essay supports the ideal of legal generality, free speech, property and contractual freedom as normative implications of the evolutionary viewpoint.
Like the winds, that come we know not whence, and blow withersoever they list, the forms of society are derived from an obscure and distant origin; they arise, long before the date of philosophy, from the instincts, not from the speculations, of men.
The croud of mankind, are directed in their establishments and measures, by the circumstances in which they are placed; and seldom are turned from their way, to follow the plan of any single projector.
Adam Ferguson (1966:122)
Key words
Evolutionary jurisprudence – eighteenth century
evolutionists – ‘Darwinians before Darwin’ constitutional
political economy – emergent complexity – roles of judge and
legislator – common law
The second half of the twentieth century has witnessed a resurgence of evolutionary theory in both the natural sciences and the social sciences. The most significant feature of this movement has been the extension of the Darwinian theory of evolution or more accurately the neo-Darwinian synthesis, to human culture in order to explain such phenomena as scientific and technological development, the emergence of formal and informal social institutions, language acquisition and even mind and consciousness. Evolutionary accounts of legal emergence, have figured prominently throughout the twentieth in cultural anthropology and within branches of economics, most notably the Austrian and the institutional economics traditions. Although American jurisprudence was quick to embrace evolution after Darwin, there has been only sporadic attention to contributions to evolutionary accounting of law during much of the twentieth century. (Ruhl 1996: 1412-1413). The situation has changed somewhat recently with the persistent efforts in law and biology by scholars associated with the Gruter Institute for Law and Behavioral Research (Elliot 1997: 596) and the nascent complexity and law movement. (Ruhl 1996)
It is not widely appreciated, except in circles such as the readership of this journal, that the current blossoming of evolutionary theory in relation to culture has a distinguished historical precedent which pre-dates Darwin’s breakthrough and, indeed, provided Darwin with the intellectual tools with which to uncover the idea of natural selection.2 The work of these pre-Darwin scholars is particularly significant in legal theory as they drew their greatest inspiration from the shining example of the common law and proceeded to establish a solid foundation for an evolutionary jurisprudence. The recent developments in evolutionary scholarship allows us to build on this foundation, a richer account of the law in both its customary and statutory forms. Such a jurisprudence may be developed by drawing together, the eighteenth century evolutionist thought, the neo-Darwinist synthesis, evolutionary epistemology, the emerging science of complexity and self-organization and the central ideas developed in institutional economics. That task is beyond the scope of this essay, but I hope to kindle interest in such a project by clarifying the central ideas of the eighteenth century evolutionists and by assessing their relevance in the era of pervasive legislation in the light of recent developments in the aforementioned fields. In what follows, I will explain the need for an evolutionary jurisprudence, discuss the key ideas of the eighteenth century evolutionary viewpoint, consider the development of that viewpoint in the twentieth century and draw some of the normative implications from the evolutionary approach.
The idea that all law stems from the will of an identifiable law maker remains influential in law schools despite being contradicted by the natural history of the human race and by what we know of contemporary society. It would be a rare cultural anthropologist who would deny that law existed before there were legislators or courts. Although legislation and judicial precedents form the major sources of law today, it is evident that law formation is a complex and dynamic process grounded in social realities that are beyond the comprehensive control of any authority. Despite its best efforts, the state has failed to monopolize the enterprise of law. As the frontiers of human experience expand, rules become modified by practice to meet the coordination needs of the new field of experience. This phenomenon has been observed throughout history and is illustrated in our age by the continuing evolution of the common law and the emergence of new rules of behavior fields such as transnational commerce and new technologies.
Mainstream jurisprudence typically responds to the presence of such rules by ignoring them, by denying them the name ‘law’ or by treating them as the vicarious achievements of the official legal system. Jurisprudence which limits its concerns to the description of state law and consigns non-state law to other disciplines admits failure. Sophisticated analytical positivists such as Herbert Hart, Neil MacCormick and Joseph Raz have abandoned the dogma that law is any command of a sovereign political authority that has capacity to enforce its commands in favor of an idea of a legal system which establishes the ways in which norms become laws that attract the coercive attention of the state. However, the concept of a legal system developed by these writers, though internally coherent, does not explain satisfactorily the nature of the legal system as part of the overall dynamic order of society. In particular, it leaves to other disciplines, the following questions: (1) How do legal systems arise and change over time? (2) How do we account for the continuing emergence of rules which not only exist side by side with state law but also supply some of the normative content of new state law? It is proposed that these questions should be addressed within jurisprudence and that the evolutionary approach outlined in this essay is appropriate to that task.
To appreciate the achievement of the pre-Darwin
evolutionists, it is necessary to recall the ascendancy of what is known as the
argument
from design. The human intellect tends to divide the world into two
categories, the natural and the artificial, with nothing in between.
Structures
like machines, buildings and organizations are identified as artificial, being
the products of human intelligence and
labor. There are other structures,
physical and biological which are considered to be beyond the creative power of
humans and hence
are treated as natural. However, the diversity, complexity and
beauty of the natural structures, and the way they reflect the adaptation
of
means to ends have intrigued thinkers. The minds of our ancient ancestors could
only come up with the anthropomorphic answer that
they were the work of a
supernatural Intelligent Artificer. As Hume’s Cleanthes in the
Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, put this argument, ‘The
curious adapting of means to ends throughout all nature, resembles exactly,
though it much exceeds,
the productions of human contrivance; of human design,
thought, wisdom, and intelligence ... hence we are led to infer ... that the
Author of nature is somewhat similar to the mind of man’. (Hume
1947:143).
This argument from design would not have mattered much in legal
theory had there not been three different types of law: 1. legislation
2.
customary law and 3. higher natural law. Legal enactments of human agencies were
considered artificial and later came to be known
as positive law. There was
another kind of law which existed from time immemorial with no evidence of human
authorship. Every society,
including the oldest, has its inheritance of laws
which cannot be attributed to human legislators. The ancients had little choice
but to assign these to the natural category and hence to supernatural design.
Hayek thought that the Greeks recognized a separate
category of structures
established by convention that included things such as custom, law, language,
morals and money, only to lose
it in terminological confusion. This category
comprised things that were neither natural nor artificial but were as Adam
Ferguson
was to describe later, ‘indeed the result of human action, but
not the execution of any human design’ (1966:122). There
was certainly
another close encounter with this third kind by the medieval schoolmen but they,
like the Greeks before them eventually
classed it as natural (Hayek 1973:20-21).
Whichever way the law was classified it was thought to have been designed like
everything
else.
The classification of the inherited customary law with things natural created two major problems for legal theory. As mentioned, there was a third type of law with a long standing claim to the name ‘natural law’. This natural law comprised the fundamental, universal, and immutable principles of justice and morality the violation of which, was said to deprive human (positive) laws of their validity on the principle lex injusta non est lex. (Unjust law is not law. Alternatively, non lex sed legis corruptio: not law but corruption of law.) The first problem was that the equation of the inherited customary or folk law with this higher unchanging natural law further obscured the organic or evolutionary character of that law. Customary law was adaptive, not immutable like the higher natural law. The second problem was that this classification suggested that customary law as natural law was inviolable by human legislators. This implication was clearly incompatible with the legislative power of sovereign rulers who claimed the right to abrogate customary law. In societies where legislation is uncommon and customary morality and customary law are hard to separate, the problem is not acute. The situation is very different where the ruler’s power to make and unmake the law co-exists with a substantial body of inherited customary law as was the case in England. This problem was recognized by Hobbes and Locke, the seventeenth century social contract theorists. Their response was to remove customary law from the category of the natural to the artificial. Though the classification changed, the argument from design remained.
Both Hobbes and Locke thought that law began only with the establishment of
sovereign political authority by the social contract which
brought society
itself into existence. Indeed the very purpose of the social contract, they
said, was to escape the condition of
lawlessness, which according to Hobbes made
life ‘solitary, poore, nasty, brutish and short’ (1991:89).
Locke’s
state of nature was a little more benign, but still ‘full of
fears and continual dangers’ (1988:350) because, in the
absence of
established and known laws and organized executive power, each individual was
his or her own lawmaker, judge and executioner
(1988:351). According to both
theorists the social contract established a supreme legislature to which was
entrusted the exclusive
power to make law. Though both believed in the existence
of a higher natural law, they insisted that the only source of human law
was
the sovereign person or assembly. Locke denied custom any legal force, treating
the legislative as antecedent to all positive
law (1988:373). According to
Hobbes customs were ‘antiently Lawes written, or otherwise made known, for
the Constitutions,
and Statutes of their Soveraigns; and are now Lawes, not by
vertue of the Praescription of time, but by the Constitutions of their
present
Soveraigns’ (1991:186). Hobbes insisted that law should not only be
designed, but to be valid, its designer or Author
should be sufficiently known
(1991:189). Thus, with respect to law, social contract theory further entrenched
the argument from design.
It is generally thought that until Charles Darwin
and Alfred Russell Wallace stumbled upon the idea of the evolution of species by
natural selection, there was no alternative to the argument from design. The
basic idea of natural selection is very simple though
its implications are
endless. Animals give birth to off-spring who have varying qualities. Offspring
who are better adapted to their
environment tend to survive to produce more
offspring like themselves while those who are ill-adapted tend not to survive to
a reproducing
age. Over very long periods of time, this game of statistics leads
to the gradual evolution of some species and the extinction of
others. One of
the principal insights from this idea is that the incredibly complex life forms
that we observe and their remarkable
adaptation of means to ends can result from
this simple algorithmic process without the intervention of an Intelligent
Artificer.
This insight discloses what is known as the principle of accumulation
of design, according to which the R & D that complex and
adaptive structures
require are attained through the slow build up of their design features in the
course of natural selection (Dennett
1995:68). It was certainly Darwin who
demonstrated this principle in relation to biological evolution. However, as
shown in the next
section, the principle of accumulation of design was
discovered in relation to social evolution more than one hundred years before
the publication of Darwin’s Origin of the Species, by eighteenth
century scholars in England and Scotland.
The fact that the first understandings of the principle of accumulation of design occurred in eighteenth century England perhaps had something to do with that country possessing one of the most unambiguous illustrations of the principle in action in the form of the common law. Even before the Napoleonic Codification, the lex scripta (written law) was a major source of law in the nations of continental Europe. The law of these nations were amalgams of the written Roman Law, local statutes and local custom. The dominance of the lex scripta obscured the evolutionary character of the law. In England, by contrast, the common law reigned in its classical form without serious challenge from the Roman law or legislation. It was in this context that the Chief Justice Sir Matthew Hale observed that law is ‘accommodate to the Conditions, Exigencies and Conveniences of the People’ and ‘as those Exigencies and Conveniences do insensibly grow upon the People, so many Times there grows insensibly a Variation of Laws, especially in a long Tract of Time’(Hale 1971:39). Hale also understood the self-ordering nature of the common law that enabled it to maintain itself while undergoing constant change. Hale identified the two properties of the common law which reveal its essentially evolutionary character. The first is that the common law has no author or designer but grows endogenously over long periods of time through the process of accumulation. The second is that common law is part of the process by which the social order adapts to emergent reality.
The first of the eighteenth century evolutionary thinkers was Bernard
Mandeville a Dutch physician practicing in London, to whom Hayek
pays the
extraordinary compliment that he made Hume possible (Hayek 1978:264). In his
startling parody, the ‘The Grumbling
Hive; or Knaves turn’d
Honest’, Mandeville argued that if all self-interested acts were vices
as the moral rigorists
of the time believed, then the public good must result
from vice since human beings act in their self-interest (1924: vol. 1, 44ff).
Mandeville’s message was that if every individual was acting in his or her
self interest, what we call culture could not have
been designed by anyone but
must be the unintended result of individual strivings. In elaborating on this
process, Mandeville anticipated
the principle of the accumulation of design. In
his third dialogue, Cleomenes says, ‘That we often ascribe to the
Excellency
of Man’s Genious, and the Depth of his Penetration, what is in
reality owing to length of Time, and the Experience of many
Generations, all of
them very little differing from one another in natural Parts and Sagacity’
(1924: vol. 2, 142). In the
sixth dialogue, Cleomenes compares the process by
which the law attains its sophistication to the mechanical process of weaving
stockings (id:32). Compare these with Dennett’s paraphrasing of
Darwin’s principle: ‘What Darwin saw was that in
principle the same
work [previously attributed to a designing agent] could be done by a different
sort of process that distributed that work over huge amounts of time, by
thriftily conserving the design work that had been accomplished at each stage,
so that it
didn’t have to be done over again’
(1995:68).
Mandeville’s pragmatic view of cultural evolution became in
Hume’s hands, an epistemological thesis. The profound connection
between
Hume’s skeptical view of knowledge and the natural selection paradigm is
not well recognized even by evolutionists.
Even today, when the Darwinian theory
of evolution is generally accepted, there is a general reluctance in philosophy
and social
science to concede that the process of blind variation and selective
retention explains the achievements of the mind and its capacity
to reason. In
Hume’s time the idea was mind-boggling. Yet, in A Treatise of Human
Nature (1839-1840), Hume argued that reason alone can never give rise to any
original idea and that the basis of our knowledge was nothing
more than custom
or accumulated experience (Hume 1978:157).
Hume observed that there are only perceptions and the memory of perceptions present to the mind. The objects that cause our perceptions are not knowable directly. What we do not perceive directly, we infer on the principle of cause and effect. Causation is a relation and not a thing. We infer from the presence of one thing, the presence of another as when we associate fire with heat. Yet, however hard we try, we cannot show the essence that connects the two. We cannot infer that one object causes another on the first occasion that we perceive them. It is only our past experience of their repeated conjunction that gives rise to the expectation that where one is found the other will also be found. Hence, our expectation that the future will resemble the past is based on nothing better than custom (id:104-106). Hume rejected the notion of innate ideas. We can, of course, construct theories and test them by controlled experiments, but this process too is based on the ‘general habit, by which we transfer the known to the unknown, and conceive the latter to resemble the former’ (1975:107). Even scientific theorizing depends in part on experience and in part on ‘blind’ speculation. In a startling pre-emption of not only Darwinism but also modern evolutionary epistemology, Hume declared in An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding that ‘experimental reasoning itself, which we possess in common with beasts, and on which the whole conduct of life depends, is nothing but a species of instinct or mechanical power, that acts in us unknown to ourselves’ (id:108).
This theory of knowledge led Hume to his view that social institutions
originated in convention not design or agreement. Social order
reflected the
build up of experience, not the outcome of reason. Hume rejected the social
contract theory of the establishment of
law and society, in both its naive
historical form as well as its idealized expository form. He argued that law and
society could
not have been established by a promise as the institution of the
promise was itself an unintended result of social life. In short,
the social
contractarians were guilty of putting the cart before the horse! Hume, has to be
read with extreme care in order to avoid
misunderstandings of his views on law
and justice. Hume retained the natural - artificial dichotomy and placed justice
in the artificial
category. However, he was at pains to explain that justice
belonged to a subset of artificial things which arose from convention
as opposed
to reason. He wrote, ‘Tho’ the rules of justice be
artificial, they are not arbitrary. Nor is the expression improper
to call the Law of Nature; if by natural we understand what is common to
any species, or even if we confine it to mean what is inseparable from the
species’
(id:484). The rules of justice arise out of a sense of mutual
need. This shared sense does not result from verbal exchanges but
through the
coincidence of behavior as when ‘two men, who pull the oars of a boat, do
it by an agreement or convention, tho’
they have never given promises to
each other’. Thus, rules of justice, like other conventional things such
as language and
currency, ‘arise gradually, and acquire force by a slow
progression, and by our repeated experience of the inconvenience of
transgressing it’ (id:490). In these passages, Hume struck upon the
quintessentially evolutionary idea that rule formation
is a process of habit
meshing that occurs through the proclivity of punishing encounters to extinguish
and rewarding encounters to
re-enforce behavioral tendencies of interacting
parties (Cf. Campbell 1965:32-33).
Hume regarded law as antecedent to
government for though men can maintain ‘a small uncultivated society
without government,
‘tis impossible they shou’d maintain a society
of any kind without justice and the observance of the three fundamental
laws
concerning the stability of possession, its translation by consent and the
performance of promises’ (1975:541). According
to him, government did not
originate from a necessity to make law but from the need to impartially
administer the law (id:537).
Like Hume, Adam Smith rejected social contract theory and treated social order, law and government as the outcomes of ‘the natural progress which men make in society’ (Smith 1981: vol. II, 710). The starting point of Smith’s philosophy is the concept of ‘the original passions of human nature’. One of these passions is ‘fellow feeling’ or ‘sympathy’. Though man is selfish by nature ‘there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it’ (Smith 1976:9). This sympathy is the origin of the ideas of beneficence and of justice. The absence of beneficence or of the sense of justice in a person evokes disapprobation. However it is only unjust conduct that inspires the stronger feeling of resentment and leads to the demand for retribution. This is a critical distinction. Beneficence involves positive action but justice is concerned with the breach of prohibitions cast in negative terms. That one should show gratitude to one’s benefactor is a principle of beneficence. That one should not steal another’s belongings is a rule of justice. A person could be just without being beneficent. As Smith wrote, ‘We may often fulfil all the rules of justice by sitting still and doing nothing’ (id:82). How does the sense of justice, which is hardwired in us give rise to the rules of justice? Rules arise because our sense of justice fails us when we most need it. We cannot make reasoned judgments before every action not only because of the lack of time but also because we are driven by our passions. Afterwards, if we have acted unjustly, we are prone to forgive ourselves (id:157). This flaw in our nature is overcome by other instincts which, through the observation of the conduct of others, ‘insensibly lead us to form to ourselves certain general rules concerning what is fit and proper either to be done or to be avoided’ (id:159). We avoid self-deception through rule following and rule formation occurs insensibly by the coincidence of individual behavior. Smith could have been more reductionist in his search for the origins of rules in the manner of later game theorists who attributed the evolution of cooperation to the dominance of the ‘tit for tat’ or ‘eye for an eye’ strategy. (Axelrod 1984). However, Smith deserves credit for noticing that cooperation is the outgrowth of not only the instinct of retribution but also of the instinct of sympathy.
Smith’s theory is strikingly Darwinian and, in fact, avoids a mistake
commonly made even by Darwinists. Smith argued that though
social life is
impossible without the rules of justice, it is not this consideration which
animates the rules of justice initially,
but our natural passions (id:89). The
human species did not acquire its sense of justice and make itself social rules
because they
helped it to prosper, but rather, the race prospered because its
members inherited a sense of justice and the instinct for rule following.
Smith
also brought out the underlying unity of the social, economic and legal
evolution throughout his work. A clear demonstration
of this unity is offered in
his speculation concerning the emergence of the division of labor and money.
The division of labor,
Smith maintained, is not the product of human wisdom that
foresees its great advantages, but ‘is the necessary, though very
slow and
gradual consequence of a certain propensity in human nature which has in view no
such utility; the propensity to truck,
barter, and exchange one thing for
another’ (1981: vol. 1, 25). This propensity to exchange, which could be
said to be driven
by the more basic instincts of self-advancement brings about
the practice of contracting. However, barter is a severely limited form
of
exchange as one has to always keep a quantity of things which others commonly
need such as oxen, salt or pelts, in order to gain
what one wants. No exchange
will take place where people have no need for is being offered. This problem
activates a Darwinian type
selection whereby certain kinds of metals survive the
elimination process to become standard currency for exchange. The emergence
of
this practice has a catalytic effect on both commerce and commercial law. The
need to certify the weight or value of the metals
lead to the practice of
official coinage and hence, we might add, to the law of financial institutions
(id:41-46).
The idea that social patterns emerge through the cumulative
effects of the adaptive behavior of individuals responding instinctively
to
local conditions was systematically developed by Adam Ferguson in his An
Essay on the History of Civil Society, first published in 1767.
Ferguson clearly perceived that human beings are able do the right thing in
particular instances without knowing the reason why it
is right. We derive
general rules of morality, law, language and so forth by observing the
consistency of these unrationalised particular
actions. Such is the ability of
the uneducated peasant or child to reason and judge, and speak his language with
discernment consistency
and regard to analogy, that logicians, moralists, and
the grammarians, are perplexed when they find the underlying principles or
general rules which they appear to be unknowingly observing (Ferguson 1966:34).
Ferguson argued, that the sense of legal right inheres
in human nature.
‘Every peasant will tell us, that a man hath his rights; and that to
trespass on those rights is injustice’.
If we ask him what he means by
‘right’, we force him ‘to substitute a less significant, or
less proper term, in
place of this; or require him to account for what is an
original mode of his mind, and a sentiment to which he refers, when he would
explain himself upon any particular application of his language’
(ibid).
Ferguson was conscious that human learning was radically different from other animal learning as the human race can accumulate knowledge from generation to generation (id:5). Yet, like Hume and Smith, he anticipated the Darwinian insight that all human knowledge gains are achieved without prescience. ‘Every step and every movement of the multitude, even in what are termed enlightened ages, are made with equal blindness to the future; and nations stumble upon establishments, which are indeed the result human action, but not the execution of any human design’ (id:122). With Hume and Smith, he rejected patriarchal and contractarian theories of state, observing that they ‘ascribe to a previous design, what came to be known only by experience, what no human wisdom could foresee, and what, without the concurring humor and disposition of his age, no authority could enable an individual to execute’ (id:123).
4.6 Eighteenth century evolutionism and the German historical
approach
In summary, the pre-Darwin evolutionists developed in relation
to social phenomena the following key ideas that anticipated Darwin’s
theory concerning the evolution of species.
(1) Human beings inherit certain instincts, dispositions and passions as part of the natural characteristics of their species. These would be identified today as genetically transmitted qualities that have been selectively retained but this knowledge was unavailable to eighteenth century thinkers.
(2) Human beings also inherit through cultural means a fund of knowledge. This knowledge is embodied in the form of convention or custom and results from a process of insensible accumulation based on the experience of successive generations.
(3) New knowledge (that is knowledge not acquired through deductive inference from conventional knowledge), is acquired without prescience through blind theorizing. This type of knowledge becomes conventional knowledge if not falsified by experience.
(4) Social and legal rules are formed through the blind process of habit meshing involving the selective retention of rewarding behavioral tendencies. Initially, as we have no prescience, we do not possesses the knowledge of the general rules of social life but only know how to act in specific situations guided by instincts. We gain knowledge of the general rules when regularities of behavior are observed.
(5) Initially state authority is not the source of law, rather, authority is necessitated by the presence of law requiring enforcement.
It is worth emphasizing the difference between the principle of accumulation
of design discovered by the evolutionists and the idea
of the people’s
consciousness as the source of law popularized for a time by the historical
school founded by F C von Savigny.
According to the evolutionists, law is not
derived from society but rather, the emergence of law through the process of
sedimentation
brings about social life. Savigny and his followers completely
reversed this order of cause and effect. According to them, law was
derived from
the common consciousness of a people (Volkgeist) who already exist as an
‘active personal subject’ (Savigny 1867:15). Savigny explicitly
rejected the idea of the initial
insensible emergence of law as custom and
claimed that the opposite is the truth. The law lives in the common
consciousness which
is ‘diametrically opposite to bare chance’.
Moreover, the law lives in this consciousness not as rules but as ‘the
living intuition of the institutions of law in their organic connection’.
When the need arises for a rule to be conceived in
a logical form, ‘it
must be formed by a scientific procedure from that total intuition’
(id:13). What Savigny meant by
‘scientific procedure’ is a process
whereby the specific rules of law reveal themselves through symbolic acts.
Initially,
we recognize the law ‘when it steps forth in usage, manners,
custom’ (id:28). Later, two other ‘organs’ of
the
people’s law appear in the form of legal science and legislation. Savigny
contemplates the possibility that ‘the
law forming energy departs from the
people as a whole’, so that the law will live only in these two organs
(id:40). Whereas
the volksgeist eventually runs out of steam, the
algorithmic process of design accumulation works incessantly at all levels of
legislative and juristic
activity.
5. The evolutionary thought after the
Scots: the Austrian School and spontaneous order
The independent
discovery of the process of evolution of species through natural selection by
Charles Darwin and Alfred Wallace occurred
in the middle of the nineteenth
century. The excitement and controversy that ensued, if anything, distracted
scholarly attention
from the older evolutionary tradition in the social
sciences. The carriage of that tradition into the twentieth century owes much
to
the work of the Austrian school of economics that sprang chiefly from the work
of Carl Menger. Although the Scots appear to have
had little influence on
Menger, his view of the emergence of social order was remarkably similar. In his
critique of the historical
school, Menger wrote:
National law in its most original form is thus, to be sure, not the result of a contract or of reflection aiming at the assurance of common welfare. Nor is it, indeed, given with the nation, as the historical school asserts. Rather, it is older than the appearance of the latter. Indeed, it is one of the strongest ties by which the population of a territory becomes a nation and achieves state organization. (Menger 1963: 227)
The initial impetus for the revival of evolutionary thinking was the
realization by Jevons, Walras and Menger that the search for
inherent value of
goods and services was doomed. Menger went furthest in grasping that the price
of a good or service was the
unintended result of the actions of millions of
interacting persons pursuing their own disparate ends. (Menger 1963: 146). So
too
are many other social structures. Menger perceived that the formation of
economic phenomena was closely related to the unitentended
and spontaneous
emergence of social structures. Structures such as law, language, the state,
money and markets result from the same
dynamic of social development (id: 147).
These are complex self-ordering systems in which constituent parts and the
whole were
mutually dependent much like organic systems (id: 129-130). Menger
appreciated that not all social structures were unintended outcomes
and that the
analogy between social and organic phenomena was incomplete.Yet, Menger argued
that this analogy, incomplete as it
is, had profound implications for the method
of the social sciences. It meant that we cannot make precise predictions about
social
phenomena but can only determine their general features and the processes
by which they emerge. It also meant that in relation to
many social structures,
and indeed, in relation to society as a whole, our capacity to produce specific
outcomes by deliberate intervention
is severely limited, for we cannot precisely
control the behavior of their innumerable members.
The theory of complex
orders blossomed in the twentieth century through the work of the Austrians
Ludwig von Mises, Friedrich Hayek
and their followers who continued investigate
the epistemological problem ignored in the classical tradition, namely the
disequilibrium
of the market and imperfect information. The idea of
self-ordering system or spontaneous order was systematically developed by Hayek
who worked out most of its implications for economics and jurisprudence. Hayek
distinguished spontaneous order (cosmoi) from made order or organizations
(taxeis). Spontaneous order was found in complex systems in which
constituent members have freedom of action but are coordinated in their
interactions by the observance of general rules. These general rules are
themselves the unintended results of the coincidence and
meshing of behavior on
the part of members responding to local stimuli in the pursuit of disparate
ends.
In Israel Kirzner’s work on the equilibrating process of markets, we find further refinements of the theory of spontaneous order. Although Kirzner does not use evolutionist language, the evolutionary implications of his work are clear. Following von Mises and Hayek, Kirzner critiques the neo-classical equilibrium model as non-reflective of how markets actually work. In a universe of perfectly informed wealth maximizers there would be no scope for entrepreneurship or discovery. The consequences of market events are foreordained within a given set of market data and genuine unprogramed change can only result from exogenous shocks to the system. (Kirzner 1997: 35). In short, in the equilibrium scenario of mainstream economic theory, there cannot be evolution in the adaptive sense but only change in the computational sense. In the Scottish and Austrian tradition, Kirzner recognizes actors in the market as imperfectly informed and lacking in prescience. Hence their entrpreneurial activity has less to do with search than with discovery. Search presupposes knowledge of the value of information sought and the cost of acquiring it whereas discovery consists of noticing information that is costless, but which has been previously overlooked (id: 32). What is previously overlooked represents an opportunity for pure profit. The human propensity to sense such opportunities leads to the systematic correction of errors that is the feature of the market process. Paradoxically, markets tend to equilibrate not because choices are clear to individual decision makers but because ‘of the unsystematic human efforts to cope with open-ended uncertainties of the great unknown’ (id: 27).
Understandings concerning spontaneous order developed by the eighteenth
century evolutionists and later by the Austrian School have
been deepened by
research programs in many scientific disciplines that focus on the study of
complexity and self-organization. Complexity
theory seeks to explain how order
as found in dynamical systems emerges without design. Living systems, whether
they be single cells,
individuals or societies need to be both dynamic and
stable, for life is not sustainable in static or chaotic states. Such systems
allow unpredictable behavior of its elements towards their local conditions
while withstanding the resulting perturbations. (Kauffman
1995:89; Levy
1992:127) They occur, in the words of Kauffman, ‘at the edge of
chaos’. As observed previously, complex
systems, of which societies are
prime examples, result from the regularities that arise in the course of
interaction among individual
agents pursuing their disparate ends. These
regularities themselves come under selection pressures and survive to the extent
that
they are retained by surviving groups. The evolutionary process is further
complicated by the fact that selective retention of living
systems occurs
simultaneously at different levels in nested hierarchies. The environment that
selects the genotype includes the phenotype
of the organism, the physical
surroundings and the cultural environment. Each of these levels has levels
within them. Simpler lower
level systems coagulate to form the complex upper
level systems which in turn provide the ecologies for future selection at the
lower
levels, causing systems at the lower levels to change further. (Campbell
1987:54-73; Hahlweg 1989:58-62). The survival of systems
depend on their
capacity to maintain their stability through this two-way feed back. This makes
the task of controlling living systems
to produce desired results that much
harder. These observations apply equally to the complex order of society.
Kauffman summons ideas developed by the Scots such as the invisible hand and
the blind watchmaker to explain the emergence of such
order. He states,
‘Even when human agents plan and construct with intention, there is more
to the blind watchmaker at work
than we usually recognize’. (Kauffman
1995: 246) The studies in general confirm views developed in social science
that attempts
to design or micro-manage complex systems are self-defeating.
Whereas the spontaneous order tradition of Scottish and Austrian schools highlighted the emergence of social structures as the unintended results of human action, twentieth century scholars concerned with law and economics began to focus their efforts on the study of the role of purposive human action in legal evolution. The idea that law is the creation of human agencies is deeply ingrained in the popular mind and, in itself, is hardly novel. Legal obligations may arise through voluntary undertaking as in contract or may exist independently of individual will, by force of laws that are deliberately made or grown in the form of custom. Obligations under tort law and criminal law constitute the latter category. Rights concerning person and property are directly or indirectly delineated by these two kinds of obligations. Institutionalists have been interested in the study of the evolution of both these forms of legal obligations. However, in relation to contract, institutionalists commence with the pre-existence of the rudimentary form of contract and examine the ways in which contract forms have changed over time (Macneil 1980) and how contract leads to the emergence of the firm (Coase 1937, Williamson 1975 et al).
The significance of the work of the institutional economists lies in their
integration of purposeful action in the evolutionary process
in a way that
highlights human design and effort in legal evolution. Yet, the differences
between the spontaneous order tradition
and the old institutionalists should
not be exaggerated. There is no fundamental inconsistency to be found between
the two approaches
and as discussed below, many institutionalists consider the
abstract principles of spontaneous order to be equally applicable to
designed
social organizations. The spontaneous order tradition does not deny the role of
human actions in legal evolution. Indeed
they regard institutional change as the
result of human action though not necessarily of human design. What they deny on
epistemological
grounds is that human beings act with prescience, not that they
act with intent. Human designs, they maintain, are but hypotheses
that stand the
test of history or are edited by it. Conversely, there is no denial in the work
of the institutionalists of the fallibility
of human design and the
unpredictability that attends all human action. What they seek to demonstrate is
that purposive human action
has a great deal to do with legal evolution, a fact
not denied by spontaneous order scholars. The key differences between the
approaches
concerns focus. While the spontaneous order tradition looked at the
abstract nature of the process of legal change, the old institutionalists
studied the actual actions that cause such change. We need to be careful not to
extrapolate from the work of the old institutionalists
a theory that human
beings are in command of their destiny. Provided we do this, their, work helps
us anchor the evolutionary thinking
developed by the Scots and Austrians to
concrete developments in modern market based economies and to gain a deeper
appreciation
of the type of pressures that influence the directions of legal
evolution.
Of the many approaches of institutional theory, three are of
particular relevance to this study. The first is associated with the
‘old
institutionalist’ scholars who highlight the role of purposive human
action in legal evolution. The second represents
evolutionary game theory and
the third emphasizes the role of history in determining the choices available to
human agents seeking
legal change. The central concern of the latter school,
known also as the new institutional economists is the problem of path dependency
in institutional change.
The start of institutionalism has been identified with Veblen’s 1898 essay, ‘Why is Economics not an Evolutionary Science?’. (Seckler 1975: 11). Veblen argued for the abandonment of the idea of the economic person as a free choosing agent in favor of one caught in an institutional web handed down inter-generationally and subject to change through exogenous shocks such as war, famine, disease and technological change. (Id: 8) The institutions themselves are transformed in response to changing conditions in industrial society, but there is always a time lag in adaptation that leaves some institutions maladapted to modern life. In contrast to Veblen, Commons took a more positive and optimistic view of the human capacity to direct the course of institutional evolution.
J R Common’s and artificial selection in legal evolution
The starting point of Commons and most later institutionalists is the
individual transaction between persons. They seek to explain
how these discrete
transactions cumulatively lead to the emergence of legal structures. In Legal
Foundations of Capitalism (1924), J R Commons argued that economic and legal
evolution involves artificial selection ‘like that of a steam engine or
a
breed of cattle, rather than like that of a continent, monkey or tiger’.
(Commons 1924: 376). What he meant was that law
making authorities (legislators
and judges) are continually selectively retaining those laws that serve known
purposes and eliminating
those that are detrimental to them. Unlike Hayek who
regarded the cultural universe as comprising made orders (taxeis) that
are created for known purposes and spontaneous orders (cosmoi) that have
no purpose, Commons saw that universe in terms of ‘going concerns’.
The going concerns consist of series of
transactions of individuals interacting
for various purposes. They include the corporation, the church, the club, the
family, the
government and state. A going concern exists before its legal
recognition ‘in the intentions and transactions of its members’.
Its
internal rules have built up through customs, practices, habits, precedents,
methods of work and such like. Law is born when
functionaries of the state find
a going concern ‘already in a trembling existence and then proceed
“artificially”
to guide the individuals concerned and give it a
safer existence’ (id: 145). The law evolves as courts and legislators seek
to fix problems and to eliminate impediments in the way of going concerns
achieving their purposes. The law maker’s task
is thus similar to that of
a mechanic fixing a Ford. They determine the organization’s purpose, find
out the problem and then
modify the applicable working rules (ibid).
As
Vanberg (1997) points out, the analogy of lawmaking with animal breeding and
manufacture is misleading and legal evolution could
be said to be artificial
only in the sense that it results from actions of human agents as Ferguson
averred. It is not artificial
in the sense that lawmakers can have requisite
knowledge, resources and command of process to engineer law to attain precise
ends.
(Vanberg 1997: 112). Commons’ view that laws evolve through
purposive human acts of selection is highly contestable. Human
acts are elements
in a complex selecting environment. One person’s act can never be a
selector in relation to the law. Indeed,
the selecting environment will usually
be made up of countless acts that express no preference at all for the selected
law. This
is obviously the case with customary law, but on examination is
equally true of legislative acts. Deliberate enactments whether executed
by
legislators or by judges undoubtedly change the law, but they are ultimately
also selectively retained (and eliminated) by an
environment that consists only
partly of purposive human actions many of which say nothing about the laws in
question.
In Common’s theory, the working rules of a going concern result from
the problem of scarcity. Lawmakers, whether they be judges,
executives or
legislators, are engaged in ‘proportioning the inducements which
collective power creates’. (Commons 1974:
365). Commons is unclear as to
the principle that guides this proportioning. He suggests that officials are
guided by ‘the
sense of fitness and unfitness arising out of habit and
custom, which is but the sense of the proper and the improper proportioning
of
limiting and complementary factors needed to bring about what is deemed to be
the best proportioning of all’. (id: 366)
As to the sense of fitness, he
states that it is ‘that feeling of harmony and unity attained by fitting
the immediate transactions
under discussion to the whole scheme of life as
perceived and habitually accepted’ (ibid). Though unclear, this
explanation
of lawmaking draws Commons closer to the spontaneous order paradigm.
Compare in this respect, Hayek’s view that the efforts
of the judge who
decides the hard case is part of the process of adaptation of society to
circumstances by which the spontaneous
order grows. This is because the
judge’s function is not to create new order but to ‘maintain and
improve a going order’
(Hayek 1982: I, 119). The judge performs this
function by ‘piecemeal tinkering’ or ‘immanent
criticism’
(id: 118). A dispute comes before a judge when a person’s
expectations as to another’s conduct are defeated or when contending
parties hold conflicting expectations. Where an existing rule provides no clear
answer the judge must supply a rule that will tend
to match expectations and not
promote conflict. The Hayekean judge is directed back to the abstract rules of
the spontaneous order
upon which expectations were initially founded in order to
devise a rule that is in harmony with that order. Thus, both Hayek and
Commons,
the duty of the magistrate is to supply a law that fits the ongoing
order.
Vanberg argues that the value of Commons’ work lies in its
demonstration that we are not passive sufferers of a given evolutionary
destiny
but that we can and should assert a positive influence on the direction of legal
evolution in much the same way that the
German school of ordo-liberalism
proposes.. (Vanberg 1997: 114). Vanberg acknowledges that neither the Scots nor
the Austrians had
a wholly agnostic view of evolution. (Vanberg 1994:
465-66).
Evolution of organizations
The spontaneous order tradition does not deny that there are created organizations based on deliberately created rules. What they maintain is that ultimately these organizations are also subject to the same principle of unforeseeable and unintended consequences as both made and grown orders belong and interact in the same overall spontaneous order that no authority can control. There are many selectionist explanations of the emergence and ubiquity of headship institutions or governmental organizations. The idea of a single coordinator or communications clearing house has been suggested by Guetzkow, Leavitt, Bavelas, Campbell and others (Guetzkow 1961:187-200; Campbell 1965:29). Campbell has suggested for the evolution of species from the solitary to the social state generally, the selective advantages of the economy of cognition (information sharing), the economy of specialization and division of labor and the economy of mutual defense (Campbell 1965:44-45).Whatever, may have been the causes, it is evident that government having legislative power and near monopoly of coercive power is a common occurrence in social evolution.
However, governments are not the only kinds of organizations found in a large
society and we observe a wide range of private voluntary
organizations directed
to all manner of purposes. Until Ronald Coase’s 1937 essay on ‘The
nature of the firm’,
the question why individuals form organizations and
surrender their market power in exchange for central planning within firms
received
little attention. Coase’s investigation of this puzzle lead to
new insights concerning the role of purposive action in legal
evolution through
purposeful action. Coase argued that the firm was a long term contract among
previously independent owners of labor,
capital and raw materials who agreed to
place themselves under the management of an entrepreneur in preference to
engaging in free
exchange to produce goods or services. Whether a firm would
arise from contract or not would depend on the marginal cost of using
the price
mechanism (Coase 1937: 390). Where production reaches a certain scale and
complexity, normal contracting impractical as
too many contracts are needed to
marshal labor, capital and raw materials in a highly competitive and volatile
market. A firm thus
formed will not expand indefinitely because at some point
the capacity of management to efficiently deploy factors of production
suffers.
Coase concluded that ‘a firm will tend to expand until the costs of
organizing an extra transaction within the firm
become equal to the costs of
carrying out the same transaction by an exchange on the open market.’
(Coase 1937: 394-395).
Coase’s theory was neglected for more than
thirty years until Williamson elaborated it by aligning changes in
organizational
structure to changes in the transactional environment. Williamson
explored the conditions under which firms would resort to markets
to secure
services or would make long term contracts. Thus factors such as uncertainties
caused by opportunistic behavior of others,
the recurrence of similar
transactions and the specificity of human and physical capital militate against
market operations in favor
of contractual arrangements. (Adelstein 1998: 63).
Williamson used Macneil’s taxonomy of contractual forms to argue that
firms
oscillate between classical, neo-classical and relational contracts, along
the chain of production as they seek to maximize profits.
(Williamson 1979:
248). The classical contract is the discrete contract where two strangers come
together just for the purpose of
the contract and also can reasonably foresee
the consequences of their bargain In these cases, the courts usually hold
parties strictly
to the terms. The neo-classical contract occurs where parties
have on going concerns but may not be able to predict accurately the
consequences of particular bargains. Thus, the importer and the exporter of an
agricultural product on a long term contract may have
to leave room for future
adjustments of prices. Relational contracts are observed where economic factors
create strong ongoing interdependencies
within a wider community. (Macneil
1980)
The selectionist nature of organizational evolution even when it is the
consequence of purposive actions is emphasized by Alchian
(1950), Friedman
(1953) and Becker (1962) who argue that even if entrepreneurs in real life do
not engage in profit maximization
through marginal analysis as assumed in the
neoclassical theory, the model holds good when it is viewed in relation to
industries
as opposed to single firms. All three theorists take the Humean and
Popperian view that a theory may hold good even if its assumptions
are unproved.
(Friedman 1953: 9, 14; Becker 1962: 12). Even if individual entrepreneurs are
not driven by profit maximization, in
the context of an industry, firms that
survive are those whose conduct approximate to the model of profit maximization.
As Alchian
contends we cannot know in advance what subjective preference in
relation to risk will yield the better results, rather we only know
with
hindsight what actions have yielded the higher profits. (Vromen 1995: 22). In a
pervasively uncertain world characterized by
omnipresent chance, the winners
are not always those who act rationally on the best market intelligence but may
be those who are
less prudent but more daring. The trick as Alchian sees it is
to back away from the trees representing the optimizing calculus of
individual
units so we can better discern the forest of impersonal market forces operating
in disequilibrium. (Alchian 1950: 213).
The critical lesson here is that it is
more useful to look at what has worked than to look at what is proposed. It is
not surprising,
therefore, to find entrepreneurs placing reliance on patterns
(rules) of behavior that appear to have been successful. Rules of behavior,
of
course, may be prove unsuccessful over an extended period as the environment to
which they are adapted is continually changing.
Hence, there is a continual
revision of plans as a consequence of the disappointment of earlier plans.
(Kirzner 1962: 381).
Evolution of commercial law
The emergence of rules of conduct in commercial dealings through purposive actions of individual actors has received much attention in law and economics literature. The mainstream view of contract is that it is not law in its own right but is the outcome of law, or at best, derivative law binding only on the parties to the contract. Thus pacta sunt servanda (promises must be kept) is the law and the content of the promise is the outcome of the law, or at best, law that is applicable only between the parties. However, it is evident that private contracts are a major source of law in the field of commerce. Standard form contracts devised to suit the convenience of particular groups of traders may become trade norms if adopted by a critical mass of traders. (Rubin 1995: 155). Trade and industry associations formed nationally and internationally contribute to law formation by the formulation of rules based on trade custom that may be adopted by parties through abbreviated reference in contracts. In the field of commerce contract and custom may interact in a mutually re-inforcing manner. Just as successful contractual terms become custom through widespread adoption, successful customary practices are selected for application to particular transactions by explicit adoption in contract. (Benson 1998: 89). Contract is seen as part of the selection process by which law evolves. There is, perhaps, no clearer example of this process than the so-called Incoterms (International Commercial Trade Terms) initially formulated by the Paris based International Chamber of Commerce in 1936. As the ‘Introduction to the Incoterms’ state their purpose ‘is to provide a set international rules for the most common trade terms in foreign trade’. They are periodically revised (most recently in 2000) to reflect changing customs in international trade. Conversely, they set standards that become customary law through adoption by traders the world over.
The role of contracting in legal evolution is closely tied to private dispute resolution. Forms of private dispute resolution such as commercial arbitration, mediation and negotiation are themselves forms of contracting whereby parties agree to abide by third party determinations or reach new agreements concerning rights and obligations through direct or third party assisted discussion. There is some debate on the question whether private dispute resolution can produce clear rules. Landes and Posner, for example, argue that profit maximizing private judges have little incentive to clarify the rules upon which they determine disputes as clarity will reduce the incidence of disputes. (Landes and Posner 1979: 238-39). Others such as Fuller (1981) Benson (1997) and Lew (1978) contend that incentives exist for the clarification and justification of decisions in the context of existing custom. The success of trade and industry associations in attracting dispute resolution business is explained not only by their technical expertise in their economic sectors but also by the reliability and predictability of their decisions. At any rate, it seems reasonable to assume that traders submitting disputes to commercial ADR organizations do not see themselves as entering a lottery conducted by persons having no regard to practices and expectations seen as legitimate within the trade.
Evolution of liability rules concerning tort and crime
The emergence of liability rules in tort and criminal law has been the subject of studies by Calabresi and Melamed (1972) and Adelstein (1998) and others. Building on Coase’s insight concerning the effect of transaction costs on what transactions will actually take place among agents, Calabresi and Melamed developed a unified theory of property rights and tort liability in which the state is seen as the allocator of power to impose costs on others without compensation or liberty to be free from such imposition. (Adelstein 1998: 64) Coase’s theory that in zero transaction cost conditions the initial allocation of rights would not matter as they would gravitate to those who value them most had been refined by Posner’s corollary that where transaction costs are prohibitive, efficient allocation of rights will occur only if the state initially allocates them to the highest valuing actor. Calabresi and Melamed argued that the state was engaged in just such an exercise in establishing property rights and liability rules driven, though not exclusively, by efficiency considerations. The difference between property rules and liability rules is a matter of different governance structures. Whether the allocation was protected by property rules or liability (tort) rules depended on the transaction cost situation. Where transaction costs are low, transfer of rights is left to contract. Where transactions costs are too high as in the case of state appropriation of property for public purposes or in the case of negligent or intentional damage as in classical tort, the liability rule requires retrospective compensation determined by a third party. The distinction between the governance structures drawn by Calabresi and Melamed dissolves when subjected to a Hohfeldian analysis. Hohfeld (1913) demonstrated that compound concepts such as rights in rem are reducible to bilateral right-duty relationships between the property owner and each and every other person. A person is prohibited from taking a another person’s property without that person’s consent not by a property rule but by a tort, and probably, a criminal law rule. The property rule is relevant to ascertaining whether a tort or crime has been committed, but itself is incapable of protecting property. Adelstein extends the liability rule analysis to criminal law pointing out that the distinction between tort and crime referable to the difference in the number of victims. He proposes that crimes are ‘involuntary transfers of a multitude of individually held entitlements to be free of these indirect costs, and it is to the compensation of this class of victims, not individually through money payments but collectively and in kind through the infliction of suffering proportioned to the moral costs of the act, that the criminal process is addressed’. (Adelstein 1998: 64)
There is no suggestion by these institutionalists that the state is either capable of or indeed motivated to engage in efficiency analyses of liability rules. Public choice theory that exposes the way in which legislators get elected and trade votes precludes such a conclusion with respect to the allocational function of legislation. The liability rules of tort and crime were developed, in fact, by common law courts through the process of litigation that resembles much more closely the spontaneous order model of legal evolution. (Ruhl 1996a, 1996b) Similarly, the delictual liability in Roman Law predated codification and arose in ancient custom. The point is that a selectionist explanation similar to that advanced by Alchian, Friedman and Becker with regard to the emergence of the firm may be applied to deliberately created liability rules. While legislatures may be motivated by multifarious considerations including the vote delivering capacities of interest groups, inefficient rules will be subject to constant selection pressures. However, while we may remain optimistic about this process, there is no guarantee that the end results will be efficient rules even if we agree on the economic notion of efficiency. The reasons have to do with the non-linear dynamical nature of the evolutionary process which presents many pitfalls from which subjects may not recover easily, if ever. The integration of this factor in institutional theory is the major contribution to evolutionary jurisprudence of the new institutionalists. In doing so, the new institutionalists reconnect old institutionalism to the spontaneous order tradition of the Scottish and Austrian schools.
Game
theoretic models indicate that conventions or self-executing patterns of
behavior emerge in populations of interacting agents
who adjust their behavior
over time in response to the payoffs that various choices have historically
produced. Axelrod’s idea
that cooperation results from ‘tit for
tat’ strategy among agents suggests that over repeated encounters, agents
will
learn to avoid punishing behavior and to repeat rewarding behavior.
(Axelrod 1984). As agents are mostly strangers in larger societies,
they are
dependent on a process of social learning through reliance on patterns of
behavior that appears to be successful. Accordingly,
game theoretic models take
as given, the idea that patterns of behavior that appear to be successful
increase their representation
in the population. (Mailath 1998: 84)
However,
it is often observed that forms of behavior that appear to be successful in some
communities are not prevalent in others.
This fact does not contradict the
assumptions of the game theoretic models but alerts us to the presence of
factors that make the
adoption of particular forms of behavior too costly in
some communities. North claims that game theory provides an inadequate account
for the ‘the complex, imprecise and fumbling way by which human beings
have gone about structuring human interaction’
(North 1990: 15) Though
this criticism may seem too harsh, North is certainly right to point out that we
will not get far in understanding
social evolution if we disregard the critical
role of institutions in the process. As the Scots and the Austrians realized,
the origins
of some of the most fundamental social norms are lost in the mists
of time and some norms predate the emergence of human capacity
to express them
in words. They arose not from rational calculations but from regularities of
action and the advantages they conferred
on groups who happened to observe the
regularities without any foresight of those advantages. (Hayek 1982: I, 19).
However, while
the search for origins of social structures is doomed, we can yet
learn from observation, some aspects of their growth and change
over time. It is
here that the new institutional economics has made an important contribution to
evolutionary legal theory by highlighting
the problem of path dependence in
institutional change.
Although evolution is a process of blind variation and selective retention,
the variations that take place are themselves constrained
by history and
environment. This is a consequence of the principle of accumulation of design
that the Scots discovered. As Gould
puts it, ‘The constraints of inherited
form and developmental pathways may so channel any change that even though
selection
induces motion down permitted paths, the channel itself represents the
primary determinant of evolutionary direction’ (1982:383).
Natural
history is a constant reminder that biological evolution often proceeds down one
way streets and, as presently observed,
so does cultural evolution.
The human
race, because of its intellectual abilities and cultural institutions, has a
limited capacity to change their evolutionary
course. However, it is apparent
that human development is critically dependent on cultural inheritance. Although
in comparison to
biological emergence, the break outs in social evolution occur
more frequently and more visibly, the process remains fundamentally
that of
accumulation of design. A major part of the cultural inheritance of a society is
in the form of institutions that constitute
the framework of rules within which
social life is played out. (North 1990:4-5). In this sense laws are
quintessential institutions.
They are not the only institutions, there being
other formal and informal constraints such as the constitution, conventions,
ethical
codes, etiquette, religious beliefs and superstitions. The higher order
institutions such as the constitutional dispersal of power,
the representative
principle, judicial independence, due process, property ownership and freedom of
contract crucially determine
information flow and influence the emergence and
modification of lower order institutions. Institutions are critical to legal
evolution
for three reasons. 1. They are important as historical determinants of
evolutionary pathways. 2. They form part of the current selective
environment.
3. They provide the agencies through which legal change is effected.
Once a law (or less formal rule or practice) is established, individuals and organizations are likely to adapt and arrange their lives in such ways that they count on that law remaining in force. It is also likely that organizations will arise to fill the niches created by the law. As public choice studies demonstrate, laws become difficult to repeal when the individuals and organizations who rely on them have greater bargaining power in the political system than those who are harmed by them. Such ‘lock ins’ result from the dependence of economic actors on the incentive structures created by the evolved institutional framework (id:7-8). Such laws predispose the legal order to evolve in particular directions. Laws that impose price controls on goods and services may, for example, engender black markets the suppression of which require further controls on trade. The immense volume of laws in the form of statutes, regulations, orders, discretions and official polices that make up the welfare state shows how the legal system can gather momentum of its own after it is set on a particular course producing consequences which no one foresaw or desired. In a world of perfectly informed persons and zero transaction costs, dysfunctional laws would be quickly revised, or more likely, would not get enacted at all. But, in the real world people work with very imperfect subjective models of their environment which rely to a large extent on their cultural inheritance in the form of institutions or what Hume called custom. The extent to which the models get revised depends on the feedback they receive and the quality of the feedback depends partially on the institutions themselves.
The idea of evolution in the sense of blind variation and selective retention suggests the tautology: what is retained is retained and what is eliminated ceases to exist. On this view, our moral standards themselves are products of selection pressures and hence we have no independent yardstick by which we to evaluate the direction of evolution. However, it does not follow from our lack of independence from the evolutionary process that we cannot or should not make judgements concerning evolutionary directions or provide inputs to the process. Deliberate inputs are perfectly compatible with accumulation of design. As Vanberg argues, ‘there is no contradiction between the notion of deliberate institutional design and the notion of a competitive evolutionary process, just as there is no contradiction between the notion of deliberate organized production and the notion of a spontaneous market process in which such deliberate production experiments compete’. (Vanberg 1994: 437). In fact, evolution itself renders redundant the question whether human beings should seek to influence their own evolution. We have evolved into a race of incorrigible, theorists, designers and constructivists. As evolutionary epistemologists led by Popper claim, cultural evolution is part of a continuum with biological evolution representing a process of knowledge growth through trial and error. (Popper 1963) While it is clear that design inputs are integral to the process of cultural evolution, it remains to consider what normative lessons concerning interventions the evolutionary process itself offers. There are two aspects of the evolutionary process that have normative implications. The first is the selection-competition aspect and the second, the orderliness aspect..
The trial and error process by which human problems are solved may be enhanced by the proliferation of hypotheses and their testing in competitive conditions. Just as scientific hypotheses seek to explain physical reality, normative rules of the legal system may be regarded as hypotheses about ‘social reality’. These hypotheses, as the spontaneous order theorists assert, are tacitly generated by the regularities of the behavior of individual agents adapting to local conditions. The social system also generates through its scientific and political activity, numerous hypotheses in the form of legislation. The process of theory production and testing is encouraged by open political systems where competitive conditions are secured by constitutional rules, constitution being understood in the wider economic sense. Constitutional safeguards of the freedoms of communication and association, the representative principle in government and rule of law conditions directly and indirectly create the competitive conditions that encourage knowledge growth through trial and error. In the case of tacit hypotheses, information exchange occurs not through formal discussions but through conduct of persons pursuing their own different ends. In this process, hypotheses are generated through the equilibrating process resulting from the revision of behavior by agents responding to trial error feedback. Freedom of contract and the freedom to hold, enjoy and dispose of property are seen as critical to the process of information exchange through conduct. In this respect, the general prevalence in the legal system of abstract and impersonal rules of conduct as opposed to discretionary powers fixing rights and duties in the individual case is seen as a clear advantage. It provides stable areas of autonomy that allows agents to utilize knowledge that they alone possess, enabling richer hypotheses to emerge through exchange. Unlike patternless interventions, abstract rules also provide contestable standards that are susceptible to revision.
The importance of spontaneous order in the evolutionary process also carries
normative implications. Evolution is a feature of complex
spontaneous orders
that occurs at the edge of chaos. As Kauffman points out, spontaneous order
undergirded all stages of evolution
and has even ‘undergirded the very
capacity to evolve itself’. (Kauffman 1995: 71) Static things such as
tables and chairs
or even completely programed things such as clocks do not
evolve. Nor does matter in chaotic conditions. An adaptive system needs
to
maintain stability while allowing its members local freedom. This is the
character of all spontaneous order including human societies.
If the members are
fully controlled the system will lose its adaptive capacity and ultimately die.
If they obey no rules too, the
system will die by descending into chaos. In
society, coordination and stability are achieved through abstract laws that
allow members
to utilize knowledge about their own circumstances. The paradox
is that adaptive order is actually made possible by the simplicity
and
generality of laws. If there are no rules at all there are no prospects for
coordination of agents and if the law dictated the
behavior of each person in
great detail, the system will be less, not more, adaptive. This is a point which
Hayek made in 1973 in
his Rules and Order (1973:49). More than two
decades on, scientists investigating complexity and the laws of
self-organization are coming to similar
conclusions from experimental data (e.g.
Kauffman 1995:86-92). In his incisive book, Simple Rules for a Complex
World (1995), Richard Epstein argues that our complex social world works
best on a handful of simple rules.
Conclusion
Eighteenth century
evolutionary thought as later amplified by the Austrian school brought to light
the nature of legal emergence as
a process of accumulation of design much like
the work of the unseen hand or the blind watchmaker. It introduced the idea that
while
we may certainly engage in social problem solving through legislation, we
may do so only within the constraints imposed by the spontaneous
nature of
social order. With reference to law, this viewpoint informs us that by attaining
legislative power, the human race did
not gain an unambiguous advantage. Once
its emerges, legislative power frequently falls into the hands of individuals
and groups
who use it in their own interests. Obviously, in such situations, the
information that is used in law making is extremely limited.
All too frequently
legislation that such rulers enact to achieve their ends take the form of ad
hoc commands made directly or through functionaries to whom the power of
command is delegated. As we have seen, this form of law incorporates
even less
information. Where legislative power is exercised by assemblies which are
periodically elected by the people, the potential
for abuse is reduced. However,
as the public choice literature illustrates, the electoral process tends to
become a marketplace where
legislative power is bought with redistributional
policies favorable to particular electoral constituencies.
As North and other institutional historians have pointed out, bargaining democracy (Hayek’s term) has become entrenched because of the increasing returns which it provides to organizations that have evolved to take advantage of it and the prohibitive transaction costs of changing it even at the margins. However, evolution time and time again surprises us by the unexpected and unintended break outs of systems from apparent blind alleys. Although the cost of directly changing the institutional environment remains high, the cost of exit has been falling in relative terms owing to the globalization process, liberalization of international trade law and new technologies. Exit provides powerful feedback concerning constitutions and law to national and territorial governments and the constituencies that elect them. Yet, there is no reason for us to be passive observers optimistically awaiting evolutionary corrections that are impossible to predict. We could be pro-active in constitutional design without pretense that we are in total command of our destiny.
Notes
REFERENCES
Adelstein R P, (1981) ‘Institutional function and evolution in the institutional process’, Northwestern University Law Review, 76: 1-99.
Adelstein R P, (1998) ‘American institutional economics and the legal system’, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, vol 1, London: Macmillan.
Alchian A A, (1950) ‘Uncertainty, evolution, and economic
theory’, Journal of Political Economy 58: 211-21.
Axelrod R,
(1984) Evolution of Cooperation, New York: Basic Books.
Becker G S, (1962) ‘Irrational behavior and economic theory’, Journal of Political Economy, 70: 1-13.
Benson B L, (1989) ‘Spontaneous evolution of commercial law’, Southern Economic Journal 55: 644-61.
Benson B L, (1992) ‘Customary law as a social contract’, Constitutional Political Economy 2: 1-27.
Benson B L, (1998) ‘Evolution of commercial law’, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, vol 1, London: Macmillan.
Bernstein L, (1992) ‘Opting out of the legal system: extralegal contractual relations in the diamond industry’, Journal of Legal Studies 21:115-58.
Calabresi G and Melamed A G, (1972) ‘Property rights, liability rules, and inalienability: one view of the cathedral’, Harvard Law Review, 85: 1089-1128.
Campbell D T, (1965) ‘Variation and selective retention in socio-cultural evolution’ in H R Barringer, G I Blanksten and R W Mack (eds), Social Change in Developing Areas: A Re-interpretation of Evolutionary Theory, Cambridge, Mass: Schenkman Publishing Co, pp 13-49.
Campbell D T, (1987) ‘Evolutionary epistemology’, in G Radnitzy and W W Bartley (eds), Evolutionary Epistemology, Theory of Rationality and Sociology of Knowledge, La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp 47-89.
Campbell D T, (1987) ‘Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought as in other knowledge Processes’, in G Radnitzy and W W Bartley (eds), Evolutionary Epistemology, Theory of Rationality and Sociology of Knowledge, La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp 91-114.
Coase R, (1937) ‘The nature of the firm’, in Economica (n.s.) 4: 386-405.
Draetta U, Lake R B, and Nanda V P, (1992) Breach and Adaptation of International Contracts: An Introduction to Lex Mercatoria, Salem, NH: Butterworths.
Dennett D C, (1995) Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life, London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press.
Elliot E D, (1997) ‘Law and biology: the new synthesis?’, Saint Louis Law Journal, 41: 595-624.
Epstein R, (1995) Simple Rules for a Complex World, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Ferguson A, (1966) An Essay on the History of Civil Society 1767, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Friedman M, (1953) ‘The methodology of positive economics’, in Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Fuller L, (1964) The Morality of Law, Revised edition, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Fuller L, ((1981) The Principles of Social Order, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Gell-Mann M, (1995) The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the Complex, London: Abacus.
Gould S J, (1982) ‘Darwinism and the expansion of evolutionary theory’ in Science, vol 216, pp 380-387.
Guetzkow H, (1961) ‘Organizational leadership in task oriented groups’ in B Bass and L Petrullo (eds), Leadership and Interpersonal Behavior, New York: Holt, Rinenhart and Winston Inc, pp 187-200.
Hahlweg K, (1989) ‘A Systems vew of evolution and evolutionary epistemology’ in K Hahlweg and C A Hooker (eds), Issues in Evolutionary Epistemology, New York: State University of New York Press, pp 45-78.
Hale Sir Matthew (1971) The History of the Common Law, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hart H L A, (1994) The Concept of Law, 2nd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hayek F A, (1973) Law Legislation and Liberty: Rules and Order, vol 1, Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Hayek F A, (1978), New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hobbes T, (1991) Leviathan, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hohfeld W N (1913), ‘Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning’, Yale Law Journal [COMPLETE REFERENCE]
Hume D, (1947) Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merril Co.
Hume D, (1975) Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hume D, (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kauffman S, (1995), At Home in the Universe: The Search for the Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity, London: Viking.
Kirzner I, (1962) ‘Rational action and economic theory’, Journal of Political Economy, 70: 380-85.
Kirzner I M, (1997), How Markets Work: Disequilibrium, Entrepreneurship and Discovery, London: Institute of Economic Affairs.
Landes W M and Posner R, (1979), ‘Adjudication as a private good’, Journal of Legal Studies, 8: 235-84.
Levy S, (1992) Artificial Life: The Quest for a New Creation, New York: Pantheon Books.
Lew J D M, (1978) Applicable Law in International Commercial Arbitration: A Study in Commercial Arbitration Awards, Dobbs Ferry, NY: Oceana Publications.
Locke J, (1988) Two Treatises of Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mailath G J, (1998) ‘Evolutionary game teory’ in P Newman (ed), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, vol 1, London: Macmillan.
Mandeville B, (1924) The Fable of the Bees or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits, vols 1 and 2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Macneil I R, (1980) The New Social Contract: An Inquiry into Modern Contractual Relations, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Menger C, (1985) Investigations into the Method of the Social Sciences with Special Reference to Economics, New York: New York University Press.
Menger C, (1963) Problems of Economics and Sociology (Untersuchungen über die Methode der Socialwissenschaften und der Politischen Oekonomie insbesondere), Urbana, Ill: University of Illinois Press.
North D C, (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pollock Sir Frederick, (1890) Oxford Lectures and Other Discourses, London: Macmillan.
Popper K R, (1963) Conjectures and Refutations, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; New York: Basic Books.
Rubin E L, (1995) ‘The nonjudicial life of contract: beyond the shadow of the law’, Northwestern University Law Review, 90: 107-31.
Ruhl J B, (1996a) ‘The fitness of law: using complexity theory to describe the evolution of law and society and its practical meaning for democracy’, Vanderbilt Law Review, 49: 1407-1490.
Ruhl J B, (1996b) ‘Complexity theory as a paradigm for the dynamical law-and-society system: a wake up call for legal reductionism and the modern administrative state’, Duke Law Journal, 45, 5: 849-928.
Savigny F K von, (1867) System of the Modern Roman Law, Westport: Hyperion Press.
Seckler D, (1975) Thorstein Veblen and the Institutionalists: A Study in the Social Philosophy of Economics, London: Macmillan.
Smith A, (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Smith A, (1981) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, vols I and II, Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.
Spencer H, (1972) Herbert Spencer on Social Evolution, J D Y Peel (ed), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Vanberg V, (1994) ‘Hayek’s legacy and the future of liberal thought: rational liberalism vs. evolutionary agnosticism’, Journal des Economistes et Etudes Humaines, 5, 4: 451-481.
Vanberg V, (1997) ‘Institutional evolution though purposeful selection: the constitutional economics of John R Commons’ in Constitutional Political Economy, 8: 105-122.
Veblen T, (1898) ‘ Why is economics not an evolutionary science?’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, July 1998: 373-97.
Vromen J J, (1995) Economic Evolution: An Enquiry into the Foundations of New Institutional Economics, London and New York: Routledge.
Williamson O E, (1979) ‘Transaction cost economics: the governance of contractual relations’, Journal of Law and Economics, 22: 233-61. June 27, 2000
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UQLRS/2001/1.html