Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of New South Wales Faculty of Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 3 November 2010
IS ‘NERVOUS SHOCK’ STILL A FEMINIST ISSUE?: THE DUTY OF CARE AND PSYCHIATRIC INJURY IN AUSTRALIA.
Prue Vines, Mehera San Roque and Emily Rumble[*]
Citation
This article was published in the Tort Law Review (2010) 18, 9-32.
Abstract
The traditional approach to duty in nervous shock cases required more hurdles to be met than in cases of ordinary physical injury. The feminist critique of these cases demonstrated that these hurdles were created by gendered stereotypes and patriarchal reasoning. The High Court’s changed requirements in Tame v NSW; Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317 raise the question whether the feminist critique has been rendered obsolete. The article considers some of the previous feminist literature and a quantitative analysis of nervous shock cases in order to examine this question. While women continue to be the majority of claimants in this area, the article emphasises that this is less significant than the fact that the way psychiatric harm is regarded is affected by a gendered way of thinking which permeates our society. Noting that the changes to the requirements in Tame; Annetts and other recent cases still do not put psychiatric harm on exactly the same footing as other personal injury cases, and that the legislative changes created by the various Civil Liability Acts emphasise this and in many cases revert to the previous approach, the authors conclude that the feminist critique still has much to offer this area of law.
Introduction
The action for negligently caused ‘nervous shock’ or psychiatric harm has now been available for over 100 years.[1] The recognition of this category has been problematic to the law, as exemplified by the fact that extra hurdles had been imposed for the proof of a duty of care in relation to psychiatric harm, and feminist analysis of law has been important in illuminating this. This article seeks to consider whether the changes in the law in Australia in this new century mean that feminist analysis of law has done its job and has nothing further to contribute.
A number of significant feminist legal theory articles have contributed to the analysis of nervous shock or psychiatric harm cases.[2] This article uses this literature to consider the recognition of psychiatric harm as a compensable type of harm through a quantitative and qualitative analysis of cases in the Australian jurisdictions between 1885 and 2008 including those decided under the civil liability Acts which were passed in all the Australian jurisdictions after 2002.[3]
The fundamental point is that psychiatric injury has been marginalised as a form of harm. This marginalisation has in part occurred because these were injuries seen to afflict women (the majority of plaintiffs have been and continue to be women) and because this interacted with the fact that the control mechanisms articulated in relation to nervous shock, while ostensibly neutral, played out in gendered ways. The fact that the early cases of nervous shock, often involving miscarriage brought on by ‘shock’ are now seen as the foundation line of cases dealing with ‘pure’ psychiatric harm, is significant in this context.
As said above, the traditional approach to the duty of care in nervous shock cases required more hurdles to be met than cases of ordinary physical injury. In 2002 the High Court in Tame/Annetts [4] ‘mainstreamed’ the requirements for nervous shock cases, thus raising the question whether this mainstreaming meant that the arguments of feminist scholars no longer applied to the reasoning processes in these cases. One commentator said after this case:
‘The Australian High Court thus leads the common law world in recognising that psychiatric injuries are as real as physical injuries and that the rights to recover should depend essentially on whether such injuries are reasonably foreseeable, freed from artificial and outdated policy restrictions imposed because of a perceived need for additional limits...’[5]
However, he went on to say, ‘Australian legislatures, however, do not necessarily take the same view’.[6] He was referring to the fact that the tort reform process in Australia has given rise to the various civil liability acts,[7] many of which changed the law in relation to pure psychiatric harm, again raising the question whether the feminist arguments remain pertinent. In this article we attempt to answer these questions, arguing that the apparent ‘mainstreaming’ of claims for pure psychiatric harm has not diminished the importance of the argument that those distinctions that remain or which have been reinstated can best be understood as flowing from the particular history of nervous shock as a claim that was traditionally associated with women.
Part II of the paper discusses the legal requirements as they were in 2002 and the changes created by Tame/Annetts[8] in that year and by the civil liability legislation. In discussing this case and some others we attempt to highlight some of the factors which feminist analysis of the area has illuminated. In Part III we consider a feminist analysis – firstly considering some empirical data in relation to cases brought between 1885 and 2008; and then we revisit some of the feminist theory which discussed the history of nervous shock cases in a way which particularly focuses on the history of nervous shock in Australia. This is particularly important because much of the feminist analysis is North American. Part IV concludes.
II. THE LEGAL REQUIREMENTS
Until the Tame/Annetts case in 2002[9] the Australian position was that a plaintiff would succeed in a claim for nervous shock where it is reasonably foreseeable that the result of the negligent act to the victim could be a recognisable psychiatric illness (going beyond grief or sorrow)[10] for a person of normal fortitude in the position of the plaintiff ; and the plaintiff is in a requisite relationship (typically one of parent or spouse) with the victim, or was a rescuer, or feared for themselves or was involved in the accident; and the psychiatric illness was the result of a sudden sensory perception by the plaintiff of the actual accident or its immediate aftermath.[11]
A plaintiff in a nervous shock case therefore had to overcome greater hurdles than did a plaintiff claiming for physical injury, who merely had to prove that some injury was foreseeable; this was particularly true in regards to the characterisation of the duty of care.[12]
In 2002 Annetts and Tame[13] were heard together in the High Court. It is worth considering these cases in some detail. Mr and Mrs Annetts’ 16-year-old son James was employed by the defendant on a cattle station in the Kimberley region of Western Australia. Although the defendant had agreed with the parents that he was to be fully supervised, James was sent to work alone as a caretaker on another cattle station. After a month, a police officer telephoned Mr Annetts and told him his son was missing and was believed to have run away with another boy. The Annetts travelled from their home in New South Wales to Western Australia some nine times over four months until they were informed by telephone that their son’s vehicle had been found. They then had to identify a skeleton in a photograph as being that of their son. As Gleeson CJ said, ‘The process by which the applicants became aware of their son’s disappearance, and then his death, was agonizingly protracted, rather than sudden’.[14] Heenan J in the Supreme Court of Western Australia found against the Annetts because they did not suffer a sudden sensory perception within the requirements of the law – that is, they were not present at the incident which caused their son’s death and therefore could not meet the legal requirements. The Full Court subsequently dismissed the parents’ appeal.
Mrs Tame was in a car accident where the other driver was at fault. In the accident report the police erroneously recorded his blood alcohol reading of 0.14 as hers. They corrected the error within three months on the form but not before the mistake had been passed on to the insurer. When the insurer paid her claims for back and leg injuries but began to balk at extensive physiotherapy claims Mrs Tame became very anxious about the delay and spoke to her solicitor who told her about the mistake. The police told her immediately that it was a mistake and she received a formal assurance that the mistake had been rectified and an apology. However, Mrs Tame continued to think the delay in payment was due to the mistake on the form and developed an obsession that other people might think the accident was due to her drunkenness. She was diagnosed as suffering from psychotic depression and the psychiatric evidence was that her inability to accept that the mistake had been rectified was part of her illness. Mrs Tame won in the District Court but her claim was rejected in the NSW Court of Appeal.
The judges in the High Court were unanimous in their view that the appeal of Mrs Tame should be dismissed, and the appeal of the Annetts allowed.[15] Their general approach was to say that the limitations on liability for pure psychiatric harm that had been used in the past – sudden shock, direct perception, and normal fortitude – should not be seen as limitations in themselves, but rather as matters relevant to the reasonable foreseeability of the harm. Although ostensibly the test was changed to a simpler one of reasonable foreseeability of the harm, the previous tests remained in a less powerful form. Thus sudden shock, direct perception and normal fortitude did not vanish as legal requirements. They were rather transmuted into aspects of reasonable foreseeability of harm.
Gleeson CJ’s view, which was shared by all the judges, was that the employers of the Annetts’ son were already in a relationship with them that made the psychiatric injury reasonably foreseeable. In their judgment Gummow and Kirby JJ made the following observation regarding the distinction between psychiatric (mental) and physical (bodily) harm:
Authorities have isolated four principal reasons said to warrant different treatment of the two categories of case. These (i) that psychiatric harm is less objectively observable than physical injury and is therefore more likely to be trivial or fabricated and is more captive to shifting medical theories and conflicting expert evidence, (ii) that litigation in respect of purely psychiatric harm is likely to operate as an unconscious disincentive to rehabilitation, (iii) that permitting full recovery for purely psychiatric harm risks indeterminate liability and greatly increases the class of persons who may recover, and (iv) that liability for purely psychiatric harm may impose an unreasonable or disproportionate burden on defendants...[16]
They answered these concerns by emphasising the distinction between mere grief and sorrow on the one hand and psychiatric harm on the other, and the requirements of the tort of negligence to establish duty, breach and causation and a lack of remoteness of damage. They rejected the rigidity of the control mechanisms used in the past because they impeded the emergence of a coherent body of caselaw. They also held that normal fortitude is simply a way to assist the determination of reasonably foreseeable harm. McHugh J took a slightly different tack which was significant for Tame. He said the plaintiff had to prove reasonable foreseeability of injury caused by shock and that if reasonableness is given its rightful place then the normal fortitude test can be maintained. He found Mrs Tame extra-susceptible when a person of normal fortitude would not have been affected.
It might be argued that Annetts demonstrates that the High Court, by de-emphasising the importance of the requirements of sudden sensory perception and normal fortitude, has finally acknowledged that the close family relationships which are the foundations of many nervous shock cases make nervous shock in such situations very foreseeable. These relationships are of such a type that psychiatric harm may be precisely the kind of harm that is clearly foreseeable. Such recognition, however, would appear to open the floodgates to litigation in a way which is unjustifiable if one does not regard psychiatric harm as real. Prima facie the High Court appears to have come to that level of acknowledgement, but it is significant that all the judges emphasised two things – the fact that the negligence occurred in the context of an employer-employee relationship and the fact that Mr and Mrs Annetts had clearly and forcibly presented themselves to the employer as people who were deeply concerned about the safety and conditions under which their son worked, and that they had actually been given assurances by the employer which the employer breached. Thus two things existed in this case which made foreseeability very easy to prove: the antecedent relationship created by the parents’ contacting of the employer, and the employment of a 16 year old. It is the prior relationship of the Annetts with their son’s employer that ultimately gives them their remedy.
Thus, the High Court’s recognition of liability in this case does not necessarily show a sudden understanding of the primacy of personal and non-commercial relationships and their effects on the mind of a plaintiff. And it is also arguable that the removal of the extra requirements ( or at least their reduced importance) beyond reasonable foreseeability – sudden sensory perception/direct perception, presence at the scene and normal fortitude – has more to do with the court’s desire for purity of legal doctrine[17] than their conversion to a feminist appreciation of the place of relationships in society.[18]
The interaction between duty of care and the employment context was also explored by the High Court in Koehler v Cerebos (Australasia) Ltd,[19] which concerned a plaintiff who was employed three days a week as a merchandising representative of Cerebos. Her contract was terminated and she was given a new contract, which dramatically increased her workload. She could not perform her duties to her own satisfaction and repeatedly complained to management (orally and in writing) that the work had to be changed or she should be given more time, or have help to do it. However no changes were made. All her complaints were about the work, not suggestions that it was affecting her health. After five months she developed a psychiatric illness of which her work was a cause. She argued that there was a breach of her employer’s common law and contractual duty to provide a safe system of work, and a breach of the Occupational Safety and Health Act 1984 (WA). At trial the Commissioner found that she had developed complex fibromyalgia syndrome and major depressive illness. He also found her workload excessive and that her injury was foreseeable and that therefore the employer had breached its duty to ensure that all reasonable steps were taken to provide a safe system of work. The Full Court of the Western Australian Supreme Court held on appeal that the employer could not reasonably have foreseen psychiatric injury.
The High Court agreed with the Full Court that the appeal should fail. The joint judgment given by McHugh, Gummow, Hayne and Heydon JJ, although it decided the matter at the level of breach of duty, took the opportunity to consider the employer’s duty of care. They noted that this must be considered within the context of the employer’s contractual and statutory obligations, including anti-discrimination legislation. For this reason they rejected the proposition in Hatton v Sutherland[20] that the only question to be considered is whether this kind of harm to this particular employee was reasonably foreseeable. However, they held that a reasonable person in the position of the employer would not have foreseen the injury because first she agreed to perform the duties and secondly, they had no reason to suspect a risk of psychiatric injury. This latter point emphasises a view of what is reasonable that refuses to see ordinary emotional responses to situations of stress such as unmanageable jobs. The judges saw the first point as of limited significance, but emphasised that where the appellant has entered into a contract, insistence upon performance of a contract cannot be in breach of a duty of care. This applied despite the fact that this was a contract more or less forced on the employee at a time when work was scarce. They took the view that an employer is entitled to assume that an employee considers he or she is able to do the job when he or she enters into the contract. (This seems strange since most contracts of employment do not arise until an employer has determined this for themselves as it is assumed that an applicant for a job will present themselves as suitable even if they are not). The obligations between the parties are then fixed unless they are varied in the contract. Despite the repeated complaints of the plaintiff the court took the view that there was no indication of vulnerability in her. Her complaints were more likely to suggest an industrial relations problem than the risk of psychiatric illness.[21] The judges repeatedly emphasise the ‘objective’ or formal elements of the case. These could also be characterised as public rather than private or emotional – the formal terms of the contract itself rather than its known circumstances, treating her complaints as likely to be industrial rather than personal if anything, and so on. The court ignored the fact that a complaint that one cannot do the work or it is impossible implicitly contains in it the possibility that trying to do the work will be stressful and harmful to the plaintiff; and they appeared to assume the existence of freedom of contract in a situation where the contractual arrangements were clearly highly artificial and coercive. To say that in such a situation psychiatric harm is not reasonably foreseeable suggests a court which continues to privilege physical injury over psychiatric harm and what they see as rational over the irrational. The emphasis in Koehler on the need to consider contractual and statutory obligations in considering the duty of care in relation to psychiatric injury in the workplace means that again the commercial context of this case is the dominant determinant of the outcome.
In Gifford v Strang Patrick Stevedoring Pty Ltd[22] the High Court re-emphasised the approach taken in Tame/Annetts when they allowed the children of an employee of the defendant’s who was crushed to death to recover, even though they had not witnessed the accident but were told about it later. The emphasis on reasonable foreseeability is significant. Gleeson CJ referred to reasonableness as the ‘heart of the law of negligence’.[23] The significance of the focus on reason and reasonableness in tort law has been a controversial and oft-discussed subject of feminist analysis, as is discussed below. Essentially, despite the fact that the emphasis on reasonable foreseeability has been applied by the High Court across all the categories of negligence, it is clear that the court continues to regard a nervous shock action as one which should be distinguished from ordinary negligence actions for personal injury, and for which special tests are needed. The requirement is not for foreseeability of personal injury (which might include physical or mental harm) but for foreseeability of nervous shock. Thus, despite the rhetoric of the court that the distinction between psychiatric and physical injury has little basis, they continue to emphasise it.[24] Gleeson CJ said:
It was observed that many medical practitioners would regard it as unscientific to distinguish psychiatric injury from any other form of personal injury. It may equally be said that economists would regard it as unscientific to distinguish between damage to property and other forms of economic harm. That does not mean that there is no legally relevant difference.[25]
Similarly Gummow and Kirby JJ’s rejection of special limiting devices within the category of nervous shock does not mean that nervous shock is not still being treated as a separate category with particular issues. The limiting devices have merely been moved under the umbrella of reasonable foreseeability; they have not been abolished. Whilst the treatment of psychiatric harm has been brought closer to the way physical injury is dealt with, the continued insistence that psychiatric harm must specifically be foreseeable (and the range of criteria that can assist in determining this foreseeability) means that it remains in a separate category from physical injury post-Annetts.
The separateness of the category has also been re-emphasised in the civil liability legislation enacted since 2002. In a number of jurisdictions the action has been restricted and separated off again from the normal tests for personal injury.[26] Only Queensland, Western Australia, and the territories allow the common law full play.[27] The other jurisdictions all emphasise that it must be foreseeable that a person of normal fortitude would suffer a recognised psychiatric illness if reasonable care is not taken.[28] That is, they re-place normal fortitude in a central place, contrary to the position in Annetts. In these jurisdictions the court also must have regard to factors including whether or not there was sudden shock, whether the plaintiff witnessed a person being killed injured or put in danger, the nature of the relationship between the plaintiff and that person, and whether there was a pre-existing relationship between the plaintiff and the defendant. These factors are recogniseable as the factors used before Annetts/Tame, but as they are only to be considered they do not absolutely preclude liability in the same way that the common law may have before that case. These provisions are therefore in line with Annetts/Tame. However in New South Wales, Tasmania and Victoria, where a plaintiff suffers pure mental harm arising wholly or partly from shock he or she cannot recover damages unless they witnessed the victim being injured or put in danger (or in Tasmania, the immediate aftermath) and they are in a close relationship (defined as family in New South Wales and Tasmania but not in Victoria).[29] This prevents most rescuers from being able to claim for psychiatric harm because of the impact of seeing injured or dead people within the course of the rescue. The statutory reforms regarding employer-employee claims have further restricted plaintiffs’ ability to recover for psychiatric harm.[30]
An example of the restrictive nature of these provisions and their effect is seen in the case of Burke v State of New South Wales.[31] The plaintiff in this case brought action to attempt to recover damages for mental harm caused as a result of his best friend’s death in the 1997 Thredbo landslide. Whilst the case was complicated by the expiration of the limitation period for recovery, the nervous shock claim was unsuccessful for a number of reasons. Master Malpass ruled that Burke’s proximity to the site was not sufficiently immediate to fall within the statutory provision of “witness[ing] at the scene, the victim being killed, injured or put in peril.”[32] This was despite Burke’s police statement in which he testified that he had been approximately 500m away from his friend’s place of residence – where he had just left his friend – at the time of the landslide, and gave evidence that he “knew that there had been a large landslide” upon hearing and observing another lodge give way. He provided further evidence that he knew within half an hour that his friend had been within one of the destroyed lodges at the time of the landslide. Interestingly, Malpass M also states within his judgment that “the plaintiff cannot now be regarded as a credible or reliable witness”, chiefly because of his conscious or subconscious contamination of his recollection of the events due to what Burke’s psychiatrist describes as “survivor guilt.”[33] This discrediting of the plaintiff’s evidence based largely on the mental harm which the judge ruled him unable to recover for is an excellent example of the unique difficulty of proving mental harm – and would seem to hark back to the seemingly dismissive way the courts have historically treated plaintiffs with nervous shock claims.
In Wicks v Railcorp[34] two male police officers present at the aftermath of the Waterfall train disaster were denied damages for the post-traumatic stress disorder they suffered as a result of seeing victims “in the process of dying...[and victims] continuing to suffer progressive injury”.[35]The statutory constraints were clear. Associate Justice Malpass there found that
In the present case, the plaintiffs were exposed to the post-accident wreckage and carnage. In that sense, what they saw was the aftermath of the accident, which exposed them to the damaged train and the passengers that had either been killed or injured. On behalf of the plaintiffs, it is contended that, during their presence at the scene of the derailment, they witnessed passengers being put in peril. In my view, this contention lacks evidentiary support. Accordingly, even if a different view were to have been taken as to the meaning of “the scene”, the claims would still fail.
The case of Wicks, perhaps more than that of Burke, exposes the largely artificial and theoretical distinction made between mental harm suffered at the scene and that suffered at a distance somewhat removed from the immediate injury or death of the victim. The assumption that a reasonable person would foresee injury to a person immediately witnessing a train accident – and not to the persons involved in the rescue of injured passengers from that accident – must be challenged. Feminist analysis discredits these artificial distinctions as throwbacks to the highly gendered way in which the principles governing nervous shock cases originally developed; this is further discussed in section III.
The fact that a different set of rules arose, was somewhat mitigated by the courts and then arose again in legislation for cases where psychiatric harm is suffered compared with those where physical injury is suffered is significant. For the courts to say that the tests are the same – reasonable foreseeability of harm – is disingenuous when there is such an emphasis on the different nature of psychiatric harm. Despite a greater acceptance of the validity of claims for mental or psychiatric injury, the law continues to see the distinction between physical harm and psychiatric harm as one worth maintaining. Why these concepts remain in the law is a matter on which feminist analysis continues to be illuminating.
III FEMINIST ANALYSIS OF NERVOUS SHOCK
In this section we consider some of the statistical and demographic issues that can be discerned from a study of 264 cases involving psychiatric harm claims in Australia from 1885-2008. We then consider how feminist analysis has contributed to our understanding of these cases and why this continues to be useful. The argument we make here is that statistically and demographically psychiatric harm actions appear to involve women more than men; however, it is more important to consider the extent to which the reasoning process and particularly the way psychiatric harm is regarded is affected by and in turn contributes to a (masculine) gendered way of thinking which continues to permeate our society.
Statistical and demographic issues
A study of 264 cases involving psychiatric harm claims between 1885-2008[36] in Australia was carried out to investigate statistical patterns that might reveal the gendered nature of the tort. This study was motivated by the need to investigate the basic claim that this is a cause of action that is predominantly brought by females. If the view existed that psychiatric harm is more likely to be suffered by females because of their greater social conditioning to value relationships, or their greater amount of time spent caring for children, then it would follow that a higher number of females would bring claims in respect of both primary and secondary claims. The data gathered revealed a preponderance of female claimants, but not as high a preponderance as might have been expected. As Table 1 below shows, 114 of the cases were brought by solely female claimants; 92 were brought by solely male claimants; five were brought by women and their children, and 55 cases were brought jointly by male and female claimants. Thus, whilst claims involving at least one female plaintiff comprised 65% of the statistical survey, cases with solely female claimants made up just 42% of the surveyed cases. Conversely, solely male claimants represented just 35% of the surveyed claimants, supporting the hypothesis that psychiatric injury is likely to be less complained of by males – and that they are consequently less likely to attempt to recover damages for it.
Table 1: Gender composition of plaintiffs in nervous shock cases 1885-2008
Plaintiff
|
Successful Number
|
Successful
% |
Unsuccessful
Number |
Unsuccessful %
|
Total
|
Total %
|
Male
|
52
|
57
|
40
|
43
|
92
|
100
|
Female
|
79
|
69
|
35
|
31
|
115
|
100
|
Male and children
|
0
|
|
0
|
|
0
|
|
Female and children
|
3
|
60
|
2
|
40
|
5
|
100
|
Male and female
|
38
|
69
|
17
|
31
|
55
|
100
|
Total
|
|
65
|
|
35
|
|
100
|
Interestingly, male plaintiffs are also less likely to be able to recover, with a 57% chance of success. Plaintiffs are on average successful 65% of the time, with solely female claimants and joint male and female claimants having a 69% chance of success.
The study also gathered data on the relationship between the plaintiff and the victim whose injury or death provoked the nervous shock, and the plaintiff’s success rate. Of the female plaintiffs, 55 brought the action because of physical injury to themselves, 29 brought the cases due to their status as mothers (that is, for nervous shock due to the injury/death of child) and 20 brought their claim because of injury or death of their husband. Another six women brought claims for nervous shock due to the injury or death of their own mother. Only two cases were brought by women in regards to the injury of a person with whom they did not share an intimate or family relation. One woman brought action in regards to a colleague’s injury; one in regards to a friend’s injury. On the other hand, 65 of the males brought actions based on physical injury to themselves, 9 brought an action due to their status as fathers and 11 brought a case due to the injury or death of their wife.
Within this small group of cases, there is already evidence of a greater number of female plaintiffs involved in nervous shock claims, which confirms some previous literature.[37] Further, females are more likely than males to claim compensation for psychiatric harm due to injury or death of children[38] and a much higher proportion of employment-related claims were brought by male plaintiffs – 21 as opposed to the 13 brought by women.
What can we conclude from this? Certainly the historical association of women with this tort can in part be explained by the clear pattern of greater involvement with children in women’s lives.[39] For instance, the tort’s requirement of actual sight, hearing or presence at an accident and the far greater involvement of women in childcare necessarily created a statistical likelihood that women would bring such actions. Division of domestic labour and childcare within families has remained strongly gendered regardless of whether or not the mother is in the paid workforce.[40] The number of sole parents who are female is also significantly higher than the number of sole parents who are male.[41] If the assumption is made that increased time with children leads to an increase in emotional involvement in those children, it could be posited that the impact of their death or injury would be greater on those undertaking the majority of their care – namely, mothers. This assumption also suggests that this impact will be emotional, and indeed that it may catastrophically damage the psyche of a person who has been spending many intimate hours with the child. This is borne out by data showing that not only do more women seek damages relating to the death or injury of their child, but that they are marginally more successful than men in seeking to recover for the same loss by a margin of 69% to 67%.
It is notable that the vast majority of ‘hard cases’ in this area – that is, cases which changed the law in the highest courts of the jurisdiction, or have provoked legislative change - involved women and their relationship with their children[42]. At the same time, it is quite clear that fathers are also enormously affected by the injury or death of their children. It is interesting to note that the success rate in cases where both genders are represented and in which there is a familial relationship with the victim is much higher (80%) than either the average success rate for cases overall (65%), or those cases in which the plaintiff is related to the victim and only one gender is represented (71%). This can be seen here in Table 3. Of the 40 cases in this category, 26 have been brought by parents in regards to the death or injury of their child. In this subcategory, the success rate is an even higher rate of 88%.This is perhaps not only indicative of the legal system’s preference for an understanding of human relationships that prioritises established categories (as discussed below), but also of the historical evolution of the tort as one primarily concerned with the reaction of mothers to their children’s deaths or injuries. However, as discussed above, joint male and female plaintiffs are overwhelmingly more successful than either of these two categories. The growing number of men seeking to recover with their spouses for their children’s death does then perhaps indicate an evolution in the roles of parents and greater emotional involvement by fathers in the lives of their children.
Table 2 – Success rates in cases where the plaintiff is related to the plaintiff, broken down by gender.
Plaintiff
|
Successful
|
Unsuccessful
|
Total
|
Male
|
65%
|
35%
|
100%
|
Female
|
67%
|
33%
|
100%
|
Male and children
|
0%
|
0%
|
0%
|
Female and children
|
60%
|
40%
|
100%
|
Male and female
|
80%
|
20%
|
100%
|
Total
|
71%
|
29%
|
100%
|
Psychiatric harm is not a feminist issue just because it is an injury suffered predominantly by women. What is as important for feminist theorists is that the early predominance of women means that issues of particular concern to women, and issues traditionally culturally identified as predominantly feminine such as the early ‘nervous shock’ itself being connected to hysteria – lie at the heart of this cause of action, and that in this area we can identify some of the processes of reasoning that create a situation where the fact that something is identified as female or female-specific reduces its authenticity in the eyes of society and the law.
Feminist legal theory and the history of nervous shock
There are a number of reasons why feminist legal scholars (who we characterise as theorists who analyse the role of law and legal practice in creating, reinforcing and perpetuating gendered hierarchies) have focused on the development of the law relating to ‘nervous shock’; these include the tort’s historical development, and the statistical and demographic reasons for considering it to be in some way peculiarly or specifically about women. But beyond these reasons are arguments about the concepts at work in the tort, which help us to understand the ways in which law perceives and constructs rationality, the mind and the place of women and men in society.
In order to consider whether the changes after 2002 have made feminist analysis obsolete it is necessary to revisit the way in which the feminist analysis of nervous shock cases has been useful and illuminating. Analysis of both the history and more recent cases reveals the complex and sometimes contradictory ways in which gender and gendered identity are constructed within tort law. As is often the case in law, a category of harm which in some respects appears to create a category of compensable harm to the advantage of female plaintiffs, carries with it risks as courts attempt to distinguish between deserving and undeserving plaintiffs.[43] At the same time, the claim that there is more to a feminist analysis of the tort than whether women win or lose, does not diminish the fact that a hierarchy that privileges physical injury over emotional harm is more likely to be disproportionately detrimental to women.
A consideration of the history and contemporary treatment of the tort shows that feminist issues are raised in complex ways by it. The feminist critiques of the nature of legal reasoning, of rationality, of the mind/body split, of the private/public divide are all relevant to the tort in ways which go well beyond the simple matter of whether claims are predominantly made by men or women. While the privileging of men over women, and masculine over feminine has been and remains an entrenched characteristic of Western culture (and many other cultures), the mechanisms by which this occurs are not always explicit, nor do they always function in predictable or consistent ways. Feminist critiques of tort law tend to turn around a number of key issues or themes,[44] all of which are relevant, to a greater or lesser extent, to ‘nervous shock’ cases. These include the valuing of women’s work for damages purposes,[45] the nature of the reasonable person,[46] and the recognised types of harm.[47] Some critiques also turn on the nature of legal reasoning[48] and ideas about rationality.[49]
The fear of the imaginary
The range of situations in which plaintiffs have recovered compensation for negligently caused psychiatric harm extends from those where the psychiatric harm follows a physical injury to the self, as in Donoghue v Stevenson,[50] to those where the only injury suffered is mental. It is most important to note that in contemporary cases, echoing the early case of Coultas,[51] the legal difficulties raised by seeking compensation for mental suffering are only seen to arise when the claim involves mental suffering only (or where the only physical suffering follows the mental injury). Where a person has been physically injured,[52] their entitlement to recover damages for mental harm (including simple distress) which is consequential from the physical injury is seen as relatively unproblematic and such claims are not characterised as actions for nervous shock, but simply as actions for physical injury. Thus if a physical injury is incurred, plaintiffs may recover for mere grief or sorrow if it is consequential, while if the mental injury stood alone it would be regarded as uncompensable.
Psychiatric harm as compensable damage is something the courts have resisted. The reasons why lie in concerns about fraud and spurious claims, many of which have deeper roots which are explored below. While more contemporary cases and legislation may use the term ‘mental injury’ or ‘psychiatric harm’, ‘nervous shock’ has been and continues to be the term traditionally used to refer to psychiatric harm in the legal domain. In the 1800s for a time the terminology ‘nerves’ and ‘nervous’ was used by psychiatrists to refer to biological illnesses which we would now regard as psychiatric.
However, ‘this [terminology] was a massive duplicity, a century-long deception of the public to the effect that illness meant a disorder of the nerves when in fact the brain was meant.’[53] Thus early in the nineteenth century, medical practitioners saw mental injury as a form of physical injury. In the late nineteenth century medical science began to argue that ‘nervous shock’ was essentially psychological in origin and it began to be treated as separate from physical injury. At the same time the concept of psychiatric harm itself raised questions about the validity of injuries to the mind, particularly if that injury was seen to involve a primarily emotional component. Early psychiatry referred to ‘hysteria’ (from ‘hysteros’, the Greek term for uterus), which was a form of mental illness suffered by women, arising from their very femininity. ‘Hysteria’ was a recognised illness, but at the same time, because it was suffered by women it was regarded as of little validity, or ‘imaginary’. It carries connotations of overreaction to imagined horrors. Further it was an illness regarded as especially susceptible to being faked, as Foucault observes:
Often hysteria was perceived as the effect of an internal heat that spread throughout the entire body, an effervescence, an ebullition ceaselessly manifested in convulsions and spasms. Was this heat not related to the amorous ardour with which hysteria was so often linked, in girls looking for husbands and in young widows who had lost theirs.[54]
These attitudes of early psychiatry, regarding mental injury suffered by women as of little importance, coupled with clear suspicions that it was often ‘dissimulated’ find their correspondence in the case law. The fear of fakery has been one of the major hurdles in the way of acceptance of the action for psychiatric harm caused by negligence, as Gummow and Kirby JJ noted in Annetts.[55] Coultas (and other cases) demonstrates clearly the fear that claims for psychiatric harm could be fraudulently foisted on defendants. The view of women as hysterical victims has had paradoxical results; on the one hand it leads to a view that women are necessarily likely (and therefore foreseeably likely) to suffer nervous shock. However, on the other hand nervous shock or psychiatric or emotional harm is regarded as irrational (and therefore unreal) and therefore something for which compensation should not lie. This led to cases deciding that emotional harm on its own could not be compensated.[56]
As noted above, the term ‘nervous shock’ was coined by a surgeon called John Erichsen in 1866.[57] He meant by this a physical impact which injured the central nervous system through ’concussion of the spine’. The first legal use of the term ‘nervous shock’ was in 1886 in Coultas, which saw the adoption of the definition of nervous shock as an essentially psychological injury adopted by counsel.[58] This case and two other significant ones which followed were all cases involving pregnant women. The Privy Council held that Mrs Coultas could not recover because this would be too great of an extension of liability:
[I]n every case where an accident caused by negligence had given a person a serious nervous shock there might be a claim for damages on account of mental injury. The difficulty which often now exists in case of alleged physical injuries of determining whether they were caused by the negligent act would be greatly increased, and a wide field opened for imaginary claims.
The reference to ‘imaginary claims’ shows the extent of the concern that the judges had about the likelihood that claims would not be genuine. The Privy Council did go so far as to say that impact per se was necessary to establish the genuineness of the claim in nervous shock, as the defendant had argued, but this did not prevent this ‘impact rule’ developing a life of its own. This requirement was particularly popular in the United States in cases from the 1880s, as Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr argued that the impact rule operated to prevent fraudulent claims.[59] Related to this rule was the ‘zone of danger’ rule. In Dulieu v White,[60] a woman suffered nervous shock as a consequence of the defendant's driving a pair horse van into the building where she was. As a result she gave premature birth to a child who was born intellectually disabled. The court held that she was entitled to recover because she was in the ‘zone of danger’, fearing injury to herself. [61]
In England, the case of Hambrook v Stokes Bros[62] removed the zone of danger rule. In a decision that was vitally important for Australian law, the English Court of Appeal removed the requirement that the plaintiff themselves needed to be in danger, but relied instead on a different kind of geographical proximity. In Hambrook, a mother suffered psychiatric injury after she saw a driverless truck coming down a hill out of control and feared that it might have injured her children who were further up the hill out of sight. As it turned out her fear was well founded. The Court of Appeal set the limitation that the shock must be caused by the plaintiff’s unaided senses. After Hambrook v Stokes it seemed that even mere bystanders could recover in such circumstances, but this was rejected in Bourhill v Young[63] and King v Phillips[64], cases which both held that psychiatric injury to a mere bystander was unforeseeable.
All these special rules were designed to alleviate the concern of the law that psychiatric harm was unreal, and could be fraudulent. For example, Chamallas and Kerber quote an article about traumatic neurosis that was frequently drawn on by American courts in their analysis of shock cases: [65]
Males venture into places of peril as much as females and so are as frequently exposed to [trivial impacts or psychic stimuli]. But the male is usually the breadwinner; his thoughts are distracted from his experience by the tasks of his job, and further he has much to lose and little to gain by developing a neurosis. The female is usually at home, has more time to ponder upon the experience, and more to gain and less to lose from developing symptoms. The independent post-accident psychological forces conducing to neurosis are apt to be more potent in her case.
This analysis emphasises the fraudulent nature of a strong reaction to a traumatic event. Essentially, the underlying argument of the analysis is that the male will respond minimally because of the importance of his rational and important public role, whereas the female at home has nothing to do, and thus spends more time pondering. The analysis also seems to imply that she may deliberately develop an imaginary psychiatric illness and then sue for it. The view of the role of the female at home is interesting; this analysis implies that domestic work is not work, indeed it does not seem to exist at all in this analysis. The female is seen as having something to gain, (although the nature of this benefit is not specified) from developing these symptoms and perpetrating a fraud on the system.
There were times when sympathy outweighed the fear of the imaginary, as in the legislative response to the Australian case of Chester v Waverley Corporation.[66] There the High Court (Evatt J dissenting) rejected a claim by a mother for nervous shock after she saw her son, for whom she had been searching for hours, dragged dead from a council trench. The rejection seemed too harsh to many, and New South Wales and the Territories enacted legislation to remediate it. This legislation[67] provided that where there was liability for injury to or putting a person in peril, that liability could be extended to liability for nervous shock sustained by a parent or spouse of the victim, or any other family member of the victim who saw or heard the accident. It took a long time for the common law to catch up to this recognition of the power of relationships, and after it did the legislature enacted the civil liability legislation to rein the law in again.
The development of psychoanalysis which took the view that mental injury arose from ‘unconscious conflicts over long-past events, especially of a sexual nature’[68] (a view which was uncomfortable for many, and less precise than the law liked) was dominant in twentieth century psychiatry until a wave of medical research encouraged a shift towards ways of dealing with mental illness such as electro-convulsive shock treatment and drug treatment that were based on the idea of a biological basis of mental illness. In the 1970s this view flowered, particularly as drug therapy became more effective due to increased research into neurotransmitters in the brain.[69] Throughout this time, the legal view of psychiatric harm was fairly sceptical. However, as psychiatry was perceived to become more and more scientifically based and as it developed identification systems which appeared to be more consistent, legal resistance lessened. In 1983 Lord Wilberforce, in rejecting the argument that the extension of nervous shock cases ‘may lead to a proliferation of claims, and possibly fraudulent claims’, quoted Dean Prosser:[70]
The reluctance of the courts to enter this field even where the mental injury is clearly foreseeable, and the frequent mention of the difficulties of proof, the facility of fraud and the problem of finding a place to stop and draw the line, suggest that here it is the nature of the interest invaded and the type of damage which is the real obstacle.
Today there are two major diagnostic tables used which are influential in legal cases. Shorter observes, ‘In the 1960s, the discipline began to wake up to the importance of getting the diagnosis right’. This led to the new and scientific Diagnostic and Statistical Manual, Mental Disorders[71] in the United States and the World Health Organisation’s International Classification of Diseases,[72] which is influential in the United Kingdom and Europe. Since negligence is an action on the case, it is impossible to bring an action unless damage can be proved. It is thus critical to establish the psychiatric injury.[73] This has been easier to do since psychiatry developed systematic diagnostic manuals, but the courts continue to have some level of scepticism.
Nervous shock and the mind/body distinction
The characterisation of psychiatric or mental harm as entirely distinct from physical injury can be seen in the cases right from the beginning, as in Coultas’s case, and is maintained, despite rhetoric otherwise, in Tame/Annetts. In 1861 in the famous case of Lynch v Knight[74] Lord Wensleydale observed that ‘Mental pain or anxiety the law cannot value, and does not pretend to redress, when the unlawful act complained of causes that alone.’
The polarisation of physical and mental harm in our society stems from Western liberal philosophy’s separation of body and mind and the related separation between rationality and irrationality. [75] In this context the mind-body split emphasises the body as ‘real’ and the mind as ‘unreal’. Injuries to the mind are characterised as wounded feelings, and emotional reactions are neither rational nor directly observable. The reluctance to compensate for emotional anxiety or pain reflects the suspicion that they are therefore ‘unreal’. ‘Hysteria’ (which, for a long time was a significant psychiatric diagnosis) carries connotations of overreaction to imagined horrors. In contrast, physical injury is seen as real and observable and seemingly harder to fake.
This perceived polarisation of the mind and body led to concern about psychiatric harm as a compensable category of harm. Paradoxically, the psychiatric harm was only regarded as real if it was accompanied by physical harm; that so many of the early cases concerned what were seen to be shock-induced miscarriages points to this tendency. The effect of the physical harm was to validate the psychiatric harm. However, by the 1960s the law was beginning to recognise that injuries to the mind were real. In his famous remark in Mt Isa Mines v Pusey,[76] Windeyer J said:
Law, marching with medicine but in the rear and limping a little, has today come a long way since the decision in [Coultas]... An illness of the mind set off by shock is not the less an injury because it is functional, not organic, and its progress is psychogenic.
While judges have frequently said that the distinction between ordinary physical injury and psychiatric injury is illusory,[77] the law maintained the distinction by continuing to insist on separate tests for each category, for a long time emphasising the ‘shock’ and other specific requirements such as sudden sensory perception. Where the shock requirement was not met, the courts frequently refused to give compensation.[78] The shock requirement operated as a way of ensuring that the causal link between the accident and the psychiatric harm was clear in a world where it was not seen as obvious that a victim’s physical injury could cause mental harm to their loved ones – as this mental injury was possibly unreal.[79]
English law continues to maintain the requirement that there must be a ‘shock’ causing the psychiatric injury.[81] However, the requirement was not so absolute in Australia.[82] A number of courts and judges in Australia have felt able to dispense with or deal robustly with the requirement.[83] The view taken in these cases placed ‘greater emphasis on the significance of the message for the plaintiff than the means of its conveyance or perception’.[84] This recognises one of the fundamental lessons of the second wave of feminism, that, as Handsley says, ‘connection is an important part of the female experience.’ (Emphasis in original) She goes on to say:
[Connection] is described here as part of the human experience because it is my belief that men experience it too; the difference is only that women are encouraged to experience and cultivate it whereas men are discouraged from the same.[85] (Emphasis in original)
Although the High Court appears to have come to the same conclusion, it is arguable whether there has really been a shift in the level to which they have recognised the power of relationships to cause mental injury and the extent to which that injury is real. In Tame and Annetts they emphasise actual knowledge and objectivity in their treatment of foreseeability and in Annetts and Koehler they emphasise factors in the commercial and public environments, in particular, the significance of the context of employment. The continued insistence on reasonable foreseeability of a recognised (or recogniseable) psychiatric harm is a tighter requirement than the foreseeability of any injury which is all that is required where physical injury is at issue and indicates that reservations remain about the reality of psychiatric harm.
Cases such as Annetts and the previously mentioned statutory reforms introduced in the early 2000s expose the legal system’s understanding of relationships chiefly in terms of their ability to categorise them. For example, in NSW, those plaintiffs seeking to recover for the death or injury of a loved one must have possessed a relationship with the victim that falls within strictly defined categories of relationship even though this approach to relationships seems increasingly out of touch in a society where the proportion of non-family households is rising rapidly[86] and in which relationships increasingly defy traditional categories and may be maintained through long distance communication and indeed through virtual reality. Whereas reasonable foreseeability alone may allow loved ones who fall outside these categories to recover, these statutory provisions will not. Furthermore, this categorical approach is at odds with the feminist valuing of “connection...as part of the human experience” [87] which would seem to encourage an approach in which the quality of the relationship between the plaintiff and the victim – as perhaps informed and influenced by any existing family relationship between them – would be valued and considered in examining reasonable foreseeability.
Psychiatric harm and the rational/irrational distinction
As already noted, Annetts/Tame, Gifford v Strang and Koehler emphasise that ‘The touchstone of liability remains reasonableness of conduct’.[88] Their emphasis on reasonableness means that the concept of rationality continues to be central to the judges’ view of the tort. Closely connected to the mind/body split in the Western liberal tradition is the bipolar distinction between the rational and the irrational, which in turn is closely imitated in law in the distinction between the reasonable and the unreasonable. The various products of the mind themselves are divided into the rational and the irrational. From this viewpoint the rational is the product of logical thought derived from observation, and the irrational includes things like emotions and feelings and is therefore somehow ‘tainted’ by the body. Western liberalism has viewed the rational or the reasonable as the domain of men, as characteristic of men and as a valuable characteristic in itself. Indeed this view of the differences between men and women can be traced back to Aristotle. ‘Men’, he said, ‘are by nature more fitted to rule than women’.[89] Men were seen as rational beings who used their minds to reach universal laws by processes of ‘pure’ logic such as syllogism and dispassionate observation. This rationality was the opposite of, and unsullied by, emotion, imagination and the irrational, which were the domain of women.
Feminists and philosophers of science have critiqued this view of rationality (which continues to dominate Western thought) as unreal.[90] It is not possible for an observer to observe phenomena without some choices being made. Further, the rationality and neutrality of the Western liberal tradition can be seen to be male,[91] and therefore not universal as it is claimed.[92] Psychological and philosophical views of reason are no longer so confident that rationality and irrationality are polar opposites, or even that they exist along a continuum.[93] Similarly, the very concepts of sanity and insanity are no longer used in ordinary psychiatric discourse.
Negligence has been said to be ‘the omission to do something which a reasonable man, guided upon those considerations which ordinarily regulate the conduct of human affairs, would do, or doing something which a prudent and reasonable man would not do’.[94] Case law says that the reasonable man is the ‘man of ordinary prudence.’[95] He is rational, thoughtful but ordinary. He ‘is presumed to be free both from over-apprehension and from over-confidence’.[96] He is a universal and objective standard against which any person may be measured. In its incarnation as ‘the reasonable person’ feminists have been able to show that far from being entirely objective and universal, in fact the reasonable person is a man. Indeed judges have referred to him as ‘the man on the Clapham omnibus’[97], or the ‘man on the Bondi tram.[98]’ Feminist legal theorists have shown that the ‘reasonable man’, far from being universal and the emanation of pure reason, uses masculine language and exhibits masculine characteristics. The use of the term ‘reasonable man’ to include women was assumed for a long time, until it became clear that what it really did was ‘universalize...particular features of masculinity, as if they were genuinely representative of both sexes.’[99] The shift to the terminology of the ’reasonable person’ does not appear to have solved the problem. Rather it has operated simply to hide the masculine nature of the construct.
Since it is clear that there is no real person who embodies the reasonable person, the question thus becomes, how do we, and in particular, judges, decide what a reasonable person is, or what reasonable behaviour is? Where do we reach to give substance to this standard? The answer must be that the judge must reach for his or her own view of what constitutes appropriate behaviour. While this view will be mediated by his or her knowledge of other cases which have decided this, the judge must ultimately make a decision based on his or her own standards. Some feminist writers have argued that this will always lead to the judge’s own view determining the outcome; but it is not so simple. The judge’s view will be mediated by all the cases he or she has read and that will offer some restraint; however, in a society where judges have overwhelmingly been male over centuries this is unlikely to lead to a real consideration of the position of women. The concern is less with individual judges’ judgments than with the collective power of hundreds of years of judgments coloured by masculinity.
The concept of the reasonable person is transmuted in the nervous shock arena to the ‘person of normal fortitude’. In the earliest cases, it appears that the judges thought that a person of normal fortitude would not have a miscarriage as a result of a serious fright, in the same way that in World War I soldiers who suffered ‘shellshock’ (the psychiatric harm arising from the psyche being overwhelmed by fear) were regarded as abnormal, lacking in courage and weak. In Bourhill v Young [100] we see an example of the view that people should not be overwhelmed by such events. There a pregnant woman heard an accident about 15 metres away from her in which a cyclist was killed, and she immediately afterwards saw his blood on the road. She developed a psychiatric illness and later miscarried. Lord Porter was quite robust about this:[101]
The driver of a vehicle, even though careless, is entitled to assume that the ordinary frequenter of the streets has sufficient fortitude to endure such incidents as may from time to time be expected to occur in them, and is not to be considered negligent to one who does not possess the customary phlegm’
And in Chester v Municipality of Waverley Corporation,[102] the majority view was expressed by Latham CJ this way:
Death is not an infrequent event, and even violent and distressing deaths are not uncommon. It is, however, not a common experience of mankind that the spectacle, even of the sudden and distressing death of a child, produces any consequences of more than a temporary nature in the case of bystanders or even of close relatives who see the body after death has taken place.
In Jaensch v Coffey,[103] the plaintiff was the wife of a motor cyclist who was very seriously injured. She did not see or hear the accident, but saw him at the hospital where she was told he was in a critical condition and quite reasonably feared that he might die. She developed a psychiatric illness, and in an interesting reflection of past links of psychiatric illness with gynaecological problems we are told that as a consequence she had to have a hysterectomy. Mrs Coffey was regarded as a possibly extra-susceptible plaintiff, but the situation in which she found herself as one where a person with normal fortitude would still have been affected. The trial judge found that despite the presence of factors which might predispose her to psychological problems she did react like a normal person. Gibbs CJ said that ‘it may be assumed (without deciding) that injury for nervous shock is not recoverable unless an ordinary person of normal fortitude in the position of the plaintiff would have suffered some shock’.[104] Brennan J said: [105]
[R]easonable foreseeability is an objective criterion of duty, and a general standard of susceptibility must be postulated. At least to that extent it is possible to confine consideration of the question whether it is reasonably foreseeable that the perception of a particular phenomenon might induce in the plaintiff a psychiatric illness...Unless a plaintiff’s extraordinary susceptibility to psychiatric illness induced by shock is known to the defendant, the existence of a duty of care owed to the plaintiff is to be determined on upon the assumption that he is of a normal standard of susceptibility.[106]
Since Tame/Annetts[107] the test of normal fortitude is part of the level of foreseeability that is required of the defendant. It is also related to the issue of proportionality between the act of the defendant and the damages they pay for the damage done to the plaintiff. Essentially, whilst defendants are held responsible for the harm caused, this responsibility is limited by the notion of reasonable foresight.
The case of Mrs Tame is extreme. Such a case creates the misleading impression that it is easy to dismiss some psychiatric harm as unreasonable and unforeseeable. In her case, it is arguable that physical harm would also have been unforeseeable, given the nature of the wrong done, and that treating psychological and physical harm as one would have sufficiently determined the outcome in terms of foreseeability without the need for recourse to extra-susceptibility as a special point. The question of who is extra-susceptible is not one that can be determined simply; what is now known about the nature of emotion and of reason suggests that they are both of the mind and of the body. For example, it is now known that hormones and other physical responses contribute to emotional responses and that in turn emotional responses create physical changes in the body, such as the identifiable link between ‘fight or fright’ responses and adrenaline surges in the body, among other things. Emotion is about feelings; it is thus not associated with rationality; but it is not entirely divorced from reasoned thought either. There is a considerable body of literature about heuristic[108] thought and the way in which human beings mix emotion and logic to develop thought.
In the legal arena a great deal of this intermingling of emotion and logic is done by the use of words, words being manipulable and allowing for connotation, metaphor and a range of emotional shades.[109] It is arguable that the great value of the test of reasonable foreseeability is its ability to incorporate more than the merely rational, and that too great an emphasis on rationality imposes unnecessary and unreal constraints on liability for nervous shock. Justice McHugh in Annetts[110] implicitly recognises this when he says ‘reasonableness is a value’ but the remainder of the judges insist on ‘objectivity’ in their view of reasonableness. There are obviously good reasons for maintaining a view of the plaintiff which is objective in the sense that the defendant does not know and need not know specific subjective things about them. However, care must be taken that in emphasising ‘objectivity’, its other connotation of ‘not involving or recognising emotion’ does not come into play. Failure to incorporate recognition of both logic and emotion in the objective consideration of reasonable foreseeability is inherently dangerous.
The public/private distinction and the ‘good’ mother
Another classic dualism in Western thought that has affected the treatment of nervous shock cases is the public-private divide, an area which has been the subject of much feminist critique. In the legal domain, the public and private spheres have been traditionally treated as separate areas where the public arena is an area where the law can intervene, and the private is one where it cannot. As Katherine O’Donovan observes, [111]
‘Public’ may be used to denote State activity, the values of the marketplace, work, the male domain or that sphere of activity which is regulated by law. ‘Private’ may denote civil society, the values of family, intimacy, the personal life, home, women’s domain or behaviour unregulated by law.
Private matters such as sexuality, relationships, personality, intimacy, reproduction and children have been regarded traditionally as matters irrelevant to law, and areas into which the law’s writ does not run. The consequences of this can be seen in the well-known saying that ‘An Englishman’s home is his castle’; it is not accidental that it refers to ‘Englishman’ rather than ‘Englishwoman’. These are all primarily matters that disparately affect women. The way that this divide operated to exclude women is exemplified by the fact that the concept of a legal person for centuries included a corporation but did not include a married woman. Possibly the most prominent example of this public-private divide is the area of domestic violence. Originally as a matter of law and later as a matter of policy, the law did not interfere between husband and wife, as exemplified by the traditional legal view that there was no need for consent by the wife to sex in marriage.[112] The traditional legal view of the husband and wife was said by Blackstone to be : ‘husband and wife are one, to wit, the husband’:
The very being or legal existence of the woman is suspended during marriage, or at least is incorporated and consolidated into that of the husband; under whose wind, protection and cover, she performs everything; and it is therefore called in our law-french a feme covert, faemina viro co-operta; and it is said to be covert-baron, or under the protection and influence of her husband, her baron, or lord; and her condition during her marriage is called her coverture.[113]
This view which meant that a married woman could not keep her own wages, make a will, make a contract, sue or be sued, gave way to the Married Women’s Property Acts[114] in the United Kingdom and Australia in the 1880s and 1890s and to various other changes to the position of women in the law. However, it remains true to say that until relatively recently the private domain was relatively unregulated. As Jenny Morgan says:
Women have been historically associated with the private world of the family,
which has traditionally been unregulated (or private)
while men have been
associated with the public world of work, the world of regulation. Put simply,
even simplistically, to leave
the family private – unregulated by the
state – is to hand power over to
men.[115]
However, as Morgan points out, the private domain is not entirely
unregulated, and indeed the regulation around it necessarily impacts
on the
private domain.
One reason that the public/private distinction is significant in the area of nervous shock is that one of the by-products of the public/private distinction as it has operated in law is to emphasise a certain kind of family (that is nuclear) and a certain kind of mother and wife – one that cares solely for her children and husband. Margaret Thornton points out that ‘conventionally a “public woman” was a prostitute, a figure of derision, in contrast to a “public man”, a figure of approbation who acted in and for the universal good.’[116] This is related to the wife/whore dualism; while the ‘virtuous’ wife works in the home and the private sphere, the ‘immoral’ whore or prostitute enters the public sphere. As such, the natural domain of woman was seen as the private domain, while men were supposed to be out in public. Relegating women to the private sphere made them invisible; it also contributed to stereotypes of women as weak, irrational and emotional.
Another reason that the public/private distinction is significant in relation to nervous shock was that emotion was regarded as part of the private domain. Once the legal system began to deal with emotional issues, such as the emotional bonds between women and children, these matters, which the legal system regards as essentially private, come out into the public domain where they ‘do not belong’. In nervous shock cases in the early twentieth century this is demonstrated by floodgates arguments and arguments about the unreliability of evidence about emotional issues and bonds. This is still seen today, in examples such as Callinan J’s view that the psychiatric harm ultimately depends on having to take the word of the person claiming to suffer it: ‘Despite many advances in the diagnosis of psychiatric illness, whether, and the extent to which it exists in a particular patient will almost invariably depend, in some measure at least, upon the reliability of the patient's own utterances’.[117]
It is significant that many of the cases involve women in their roles as mothers. In Bourhill v Young[118] the court held the plaintiff could recover if she was within the zone of physical risk. However, in Bourhill, the plaintiff was a pregnant woman who heard, but could not see an accident which took place some 15 metres away from her. Because she did not fear for her own safety she could not recover damages, even though the court accepted that the shock caused the stillbirth of her child, as the court could not accept that the woman’s feelings for the child could foreseeably lead to psychiatric harm.
However, in Hambrook v Stokes Brothers[119] Bankes LJ was scornful of the ‘zone of danger’ test, basing his analysis on ‘the good mother’:
Assume two mothers crossing this street at the same time when this lorry comes thundering down, each holding a small child by the hand. One mother is courageous and devoted to her child. She is terrified, but thinks only of the damage to the child, and not at all about herself. The other woman is timid and lacking in the motherly instinct. She is also terrified, but thinks only of the damage to herself and not at all about her child. The health of both mothers is seriously affected by the mental shock occasioned by the fright. Can any real distinction be drawn between the two cases? Will the law recognise a cause of action in the case of the less deserving mother, and none in the case of the more deserving one? Does the law say that the defendant ought reasonably to have anticipated the non-natural feeling of the timid mother, and not the natural feeling of the courageous mother? I think not.
Thus the consideration of motherly behaviour shaped the law. Chamallas and Kerber[120] argue that the early cases of nervous shock did recognise that this was a gendered harm, which women were more likely to suffer, but that later analysis began to ignore this. They note both the dualism of physical and emotional harm (discussed above) and that much of the analysis of the cases of nervous shock arises from the way that motherhood is constructed. Unfortunately, the use of the mother-love paradigm disadvantages women, even though it allows them to recover damages. The majority of cases rely on the close physical presence of mothers to their children in order to found a case of nervous shock.[121] This derives from a view of the ‘good’ mother as the major if not sole carer of her children, physically as well as emotionally present, and caring for the children instead of wage-earning. It also assumes that it is unusual for mothers to be wage earners, when the fact is that historically the vast majority of women have had paid work (and been the major carers for the children). It also ignores the fact that the link between mothers and children (as between fathers and children) is emotional, not based on mere physical proximity.
The treatment of women as mothers and as defined by their sex raises some of the most central issues of feminist theory. Early feminists, drawing on liberal theory, argued for equality of treatment for women – for women to be treated like men. Other feminists, such as Luce Iragaray, who emphasises the special nature of women and challenges both patriarchy and biological determinist theories[122] have argued that this is impossible. Iragaray insists on the separation of womanhood from motherhood. Iragaray’s theory of ‘different voice’ is interesting because she directly critiques psychoanalysis’ treatment of women and sexuality as ignoring the patriarchal order and therefore misunderstanding women. On the other hand, Carol Gilligan’s work draws on developmental psychology to suggest that there is something distinctive about women’s voice as an empirical matter.[123] In turn she is criticised by Catharine MacKinnon who says any such voice is merely the voice of the oppressed.[124] It is striking however, when considering the nervous shock cases, how rarely female voices are considered or heard, and how as plaintiffs they are regarded as self-serving and unreliable, or even ‘fraudulent’, as seen above.
Some feminist theorists such as Leslie Bender,[125] have argued that the male standard has been the chief standard used in determining what is foreseeable as psychiatric harm. That is, that psychiatric harm is not likely to happen because a person of normal fortitude would not suffer it. Bender and others contend that the person of normal fortitude in their view has been constructed by (male) judges and therefore is unemotional and mentally ‘tough’, as illustrated by the remarks of Lord Porter in Bourhill v Young and Chief Justice Latham in Chester v Waverley Council, both quoted above. As Bender has pointed out, the rate at which mothers have been held not to foreseeably suffer from nervous shock suggests that mothers have, or should have ‘a high degree of robustness’. Chester v Waverley Council exemplifies the early narrow treatment of psychiatric harm. In that case a mother had been searching for her child for several hours. Ultimately he was found drowned in a ditch which council workers had failed to fence off. The majority held that the mother could not recover because it was not foreseeable that she might suffer psychiatric harm. Hocking and Smith note that,[126]
[T]he majority judgments fully illustrate the inherent lack of legal weight accorded women’s work in caring for family members. However, it also illustrates, through the powerful dissenting judgment of Evatt J, that certain members of the judiciary have always possessed the insight and humanity which feminist jurisprudence has criticised as lacking in so many male judges.
Although she was not allowed to recover, the mother in Chester has become almost iconic and Evatt J’s judgment has become the most powerful view of her:
There was evidence that from the moment when the plaintiff discovered that her child was missing she searched for him without intermission... Like most mothers placed in a similar situation, she was tortured between the fear that he had been drowned and the hope that either he was not in the trench at all, or that, if he was, a quick recovery of his body and the immediate application of artificial respiration might save him from death.’ [He described her as ‘In this agonized and distracted state of mind’ and quoted from William Blake, and then went on]...so far the argument rests upon the contention that no other parents would have suffered shock and illness from the ordeal undergone by Mrs Chester. I think this is a mere assertion and is contradicted by all human experience. I think that only “the most indurate heart” could have gone through the experience without serious physical consequences.’
Later this view of ‘the good mother’ allowed the extension of the position where a person could be compensated to the situation where the mother did not see the children until the aftermath of the accident as in McLoughlin v O’Brian, where the mother came to the hospital to be told one child had been killed and her husband and other children were severely injured; similarly in Petrie v Dowling,[127] where the ‘good mother’ perception was used to extend to recovery on being told of her daughter’s death. By that time feminist critiques of the artificiality of the sudden sensory perception test had begun to have purchase. Once this had occurred, then this principle could be extended to apply to both mother and father in Annetts. Arguably, this can be viewed as reflective of society’s changing perception of the relationships of both mother and father with their children, and the emotional bonds generated in both men and women. However, despite the reduced emphasis on normal fortitude in Annetts/Tame the legislation has re-emphasised it, making Bender’s remarks of continuing pertinence. The ‘good mother’ is also mentally tough.
Weaving it all together
The area of psychiatric harm or ‘nervous shock’ is on the ‘wrong’ side of each of the dualisms discussed – on the side of the mind, the irrational, and the private domain, where patriarchal law has traditionally favoured the body, the rational and the public domain, each of these areas being the domain of men. Because they have been the domain of men, men have shaped them and fitted the law onto their own templates. Because ‘nervous shock’ cases have been more often brought by women and the idea of psychiatric harm is seen as weak, feminine, of the irrational mind or emotions rather than masculine, of the body and of the rational mind, it has been extremely difficult for the women (and men – because, of course, men are also capable of emotion) who have suffered this kind of injury to have the injury recognised and the cause of action vindicated. Why? Because the law’s preference for the provable, the rational and the physical, bodily harm make it hard to prove the existence of an emotional harm, and because the need to demonstrate a causal link between the harm and a wrong is difficult in these cases, due to the plethora of variables known to affect one’s state of mind. The requirement of a reasonably foreseeable mental illness is itself paradoxical when it is clear that mental illness is by definition abnormal.
All these areas of feminist concern interact in relation to cases of nervous shock. It can be seen that the concept of the good mother interacts with the concept of the private domain and the concept of fraudulent claims for imaginary harms. While we no longer see these concepts themselves discussed in the cases, their ghosts linger in comments about the dangers of simply allowing recovery for pure psychiatric harm, how easy it is to dissemble and how much the plaintiff’s word must be relied on for that. The fact that back pain must be reported by the plaintiff in a case of personal injury damages and the plaintiff’s word is all the evidence there is does not seem to create the view that we should have a special category of negligence for back pain, but psychiatric harm is still seen as a special case, and the legislation takes us back to a situation where psychiatric harm requires extra hurdles.
Patriarchy’s treatment of women as ‘hysterical’ and of
feelings as ‘irrational’ is spectacularly illuminated
in the still
not quite concluded debate about whether mental harm is as valid as physical
harm and whether they can be valued the
same way. Thus, even where it is a man
whose mental illness is being considered, he is also affected by patriarchal
attitudes to
mental illness and irrationality, which are inclined to see both
qualities as undesirable weaknesses. Similarly illuminated by feminist
analysis
are the ideas of the ‘normal’ and ‘good’ mother and the
foreseeability of her reaction to her child’s
death or injury and the
public/private distinction and the consequences of the intervention of the
public sphere (through the law)
on typically private matters of emotion and the
mind. All these factors show that nervous shock cases are peculiarly useful in
illuminating
feminist issues in the domain of tort law and that this continues
to be so.
IV. CONCLUSION
This paper has attempted to show in the Australian context that the reasons
why nervous shock is a feminist issue are complex and
that feminist issues have
not been entirely resolved by the changes in the common law created by the
cases; and that many of the
factors which feminist analysis most seriously
challenged have been reintroduced in the civil liability legislation. We have
shown
that women are statistically more likely than men to be the plaintiff in a
nervous shock claim, both in claims in respect of themselves
and in claims as
parents. The cultural and stereotypical assignment of gender roles issues is
another contributing factor - the
early development of a connection between
nervous shock and miscarriage is significant in this; even now women do the
majority of
childcare and therefore are the people most likely to be harmed in
the nervous shock scenario involving injured children. Women are
encouraged to
be interested in emotion and feelings and therefore are also more likely to
notice or be willing to state that there
is a problem than men.
Although the High Court in Annetts/Tame and Koehler did change the requirements for nervous shock cases, it is not clear that it did this entirely for reasons that undermine the feminist critique, nor that the concept of psychiatric harm as a real injury has been completely accepted. The emphasis on the employer/employee relationship allowed the Annetts were able to put themselves on the privileged side of the dualisms of public and private, rational and irrational and thereby win their case. Mrs Koehler’s psychiatric harm was seen as her problem because she had voluntarily entered into a contract of employment. The fact that the rules were changed largely in the context of an employer/employee relationship suggests that it is easier to recognise harm within the context of such a ‘public’ relationship than it is to look at the pure relational harm which springs out of the private relationship of parent and child or even the private life of the individual’s mind. The continuing emphasis on the requirement that reasonable foreseeability of psychiatric harm be shown rather than any personal harm in itself shows that the physical/mental distinction still has significant power in the law of negligence and that feminist critiques continue to have value in this category of negligence. This is reinforced by the legislative schemes which have reinstated the law which applied before Annetts/Tame and which amply demonstrate that psychiatric harm remains likely to be seen as fraudulent or imaginary and that allowing a duty of care to arise in respect of it is something to be vigilantly guarded against. The continuing distrust of and special requirements to establish the cause of action for negligently causing nervous shock have their roots in a gendered approach to categories of harm which continues to sustain cultural responses to psychiatric harm. The feminist critique has not yet been rendered obsolete.
[*]
Prue Vines is Professor, Mehera San Roque is Lecturer and Emily Rumble is a
student at the UNSW Law
School.
[1]
Victorian Railway Commissioners v Coultas [1886] VicLawRp 182; (1886) 12 VLR 895; (1888) 13
App Cas 222.
[2]
Martha Chamallas and Linda Kerber, ‘Women, Mothers and the Law of Fright:
a History’ (1990)88Michigan Law Review 814; Leslie Bender,
‘Feminist (Re)Torts: Thoughts on the Liability Crisis, Mass torts, Power
and Responsibilities’ (1990) Duke Law Journal 848; Leslie Bender
‘ A Lawyer’s Primer on Feminist Theory and Tort’ (1988) 38
J Legal Education 3; Lucinda Finley, ‘Breaking the Silence: Including
Women’s Issues in a Torts Course’ (1989) 1 Yale Journal of Law
and Feminism 41; Elizabeth Handsley, ‘Mental Injury Occasioned by Harm
to Another: a Feminist Critique’ (1996) 14 Law and
Inequality : a Journal of Theory and Practice
391.
[3] ACT Civil
Law (Wrongs ) Act; NSW Civil Liability Act 2002; NT Personal Injuries
(Liabilities and Damages) Act; NT Personal Injuries (Civil Claims) Act ; Qld
Civil Liability Act 2003; Qld
Personal Injuries Proceedings Act 2002; SA Civil
Liability Act 2002; Tas Civil Liability Act 2002; Vic Wrongs Act 1958; WA Civil
Liability Act
2002.
[4] Tame v
NSW; Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR
317.
[5] Peter
Handford, Mullany and Handford’s Tort Liability for Psychiatric Damage,
2nd ed., 2006,
[1.180].
[6]
Ibid.
[7] ACT Civil
Law (Wrongs ) Act; NSW Civil Liability Act 2002; Tas Civil Liability Act 2002;
SA Civil Liability Act 2002; Vic Wrongs Act 1958; WA Civil Liability Act
2002.
[8] Tame v
NSW Police; Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd ([2002] HCA 35; 2002) 211 CLR 317
(hereafter
‘Tame/Annetts’.
[9]
Ibid
[10] The
insistence on the distinction between psychiatric harm and mere mental distress
or ‘grief and sorrow’ does not exist
in the United States. While
this distinction probably helps to keep the floodgates closed, the fact that the
distinction does not
really exist in psychiatry makes it
problematic.
[11]
This was the situation in Jaensch v Coffey[1984] HCA 52; (1984) 155 CLR 549 and was well
accepted, although both McLoughlin v O’Brian [1982] UKHL 3; [1983] 1 AC 410
in England and Jaensch v Coffey in Australia extended the
‘presence’ requirement to include presence at the aftermath of an
accident, including the hospital.
See generally, Peter Handford, note 5
above.
[12]
Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 532; Chapman v Hearse [1961] HCA 46; (1961) 106
CLR 112.
[13]
Tame v New South Wales; Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd
[2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317 (hereafter
‘Annetts’).
[14]
Annetts [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317 per Gleeson CJ at
337.
[15] Note that
after Page v Smith [1996] 2 AC 455 the English approach to
psychiatric harm differed sharply from that elsewhere in that it emphasised the
distinction between primary
victims like Mrs Tame and secondary victims like
the Annetts. In England the test for primary victims is foreseeability of some
kind of injury alone, while for secondary victims it requires foreseeability of
psychiatric harm to a person of normal fortitude
and the special factors such as
proximity in time and space, etc. Other jurisdictions including Australia
require that foreseeability
of psychiatric harm be established for both primary
and secondary
victims.
[16]
Annetts [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317 at
381
[17] Gummow and
Kirby JJ said at [191] ‘Moreover, the emergence of a coherent body of case
law is impeded, not assisted, by such
a fixed system of categories. Rigid
distinctions of the type required by the ‘direct perception’ rule
inevitably generate
exceptions and new categories, like the “immediate
aftermath” qualification, as the inadequacies of the recognised categories
become apparent and “hard cases” are accommodated...As the
categories and exceptions proliferate, the reasoning and outcomes
in the cases
become increasingly detached from the rationale supporting the cause of
action.’
[18]
The view that a feminist view necessarily emphasises our interconnectedness has
been argued and argued against in relation to tort
law – for example, L
Bender, “A Lawyer’s Primer on Feminist Theory and Tort’
(1988) 38 J Legal Education 3; L Finley, ‘A break in the silence:
including women’s issues in a torts course ‘ (1989) 1 Yale J of
Law and Feminism 41; L McClain ‘Atomistic Man Revisited: Liberalism,
Connection and Feminist Jurisprudence ‘ (1992) 65 Southern California
LR 1171. Argument against this idea comes from other feminists, for
example, Catherine MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified, 1986 who argues that
this interconnectedness merely reflects the position of women as
oppressed.
[19]
(2005) 222 CLR 44 [2005] HCA
15.
[20] [2002] EWCA Civ 76; [2002] 2
All ER 1.
[21]
McHugh, Gummow, Hayne and Hayden JJ at
[41].
[22] (2003)
214 CLR 269.
[23]
At [14].
[24] See
Hayne J at [259] ; Gaudron J at [46]; Callinan J at [308 ] :‘Psychiatric
illness is different from physical injury in one
respect at least. Usually the
traumatic physical injury has occurred, and the effect of it, except perhaps for
some soft tissue injuries,
can be objectively verified and measured by skilled
physical examination, modern pathology and radiology. Despite many advances in
the diagnosis of psychiatric illness, whether, and the extent to which it exists
in a particular patient will almost invariably depend,
in some measure at least,
upon the reliability of the patient’s own utterances’ and Callinan J
at [334] :’Nervous
shock cases, as with economic torts, do stand in a
separate category from cases of torts involving physical
injury...because...although
susceptibility to psychiatric injury may vary from
person to person, everyone knows, and can foresee, that physical trauma will
inevitably
cause physical
injury’
[25]
At [5].
[26] NSW
Civil Liability Act 2002 s 32; Tas Civil Liability Act 2002 s 34; SA Civil
Liability Act 2002, s 33; Vic Wrongs Act 1958, s
72
[27] Qld: no
relevant provision; WA Civil Liability Act 2002 s 5S; ACT Civil Law (Wrongs) Act
2002 s 34; NT Law Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) Act s
25.
[28] Civil Law
(Wrongs ) Act s 34 (1) NSW Civil Liability Act 2002 s 32 (1); Tas Civil
Liability Act 2002 s 34(1); SA Civil Liability Act 2002, s 33(1); Vic Wrongs Act
1958, s 72(1); WA Civil Liability Act 2001
s5S(1).
[29] NSW
Civil Liability Act 2002 s
30.
[30] Note, for
example, that in NSW the CLA does not apply to employer-employee claims : s 3B;
and the Workers Compensation Act 1987 (NSW) provides s151P: 'No damages
for psychological or psychiatric injury are to be awarded in respect of an
injury except in favour
of (a) the injured worker, or (b) a parent, spouse,
brother, sister or child of the injured or deceased person who, as a consequence
of the injury to the injured person or the death of the deceased person,
has suffered a demonstrable psychological or psychiatric
illness and not merely
a normal emotional or cultural grief
reaction.'
[31]
Burke v State of New South Wales [2004] NSWSC
725.
[32] s30(2)(a)
NSW Civil Liability Act
2002.
[33] Burke
v State of New South Wales [2004] NSWSC
725.
[34] Wicks
v Railcorp [2007] NSWSC
1346.
[35] Wicks
v Railcorp [2007] NSWSC 1346 at
[21].
[36] All
reported cases for the period. Each case decided is counted only once even if
there is more than one decision on it - thus
a case which begins in the Supreme
Court and is heard three times culminating in the High Court is counted as
one.
[37] The ratio
of female plaintiffs to male of 301 cases in early twentieth century US cases
was 5:1 in a study carried out by HW Smith:
‘Relation of Emotions to
Injury and Disease: Legal Liability for Psychic Stimuli’ (1944) 30 Va L
Rev 193, cited in Chamallas and Kerber ’Women, Mothers and the Law of
Fright’ (1990) 88 Mich L Rev 814 at 846. We have been able to
find no other studies of these
ratios.
[38] In
relation to claims for themselves, 31 of the females and 7 of the males brought
claims arising out of sexual assault; and 17 of
the males and 9 of the
females’ claims arose out of
employment.
[39]
The Australian Bureau of Statistics estimates that there were 5.3 million
mothers in Australia in 2000. At this time there were at
least 1.75 million
males who were fathers with children less than 15 years old. Of these, 93% were
employed or looking for work.
83% were employed full time. Of the fathers with
young children, few were likely to be unpartnered or spend significant time with
the children. In June 1999 27% of fathers compared with 68% of mothers used
jobsharing or other family-friendly arrangements to care
for children under 12
years old. This implies that a higher proportion of employed fathers than
employed mothers had partners who
stayed at home to care for children.
Regardless of their employment status mothers generally spend at least twice as
much time on
childcare as the father. In 2000 86% of one-parent families had a
female parent. <www.abs.gov.au>: accessed 29.2
2008.
[40] Time use
studies have repeatedly shown that women continue to perform the majority of
childcare tasks within a family, as well as
spend more time on their own with
children. L Craig, Time to Care: A comparison of how couple and sole parent
households allocate time to work and children (Social Policy Research Centre
Discussion Paper No. 133, June 2004) divides childcare activities into four
different categories;
physical care, child-related travel, interactive care and
passive childcare. Across all categories mothers spend substantially more
time
with their children than fathers, and much of the time fathers spend with their
children is in the company of the mother. See
also A Cross-National
Comparison of the Impact of Children on Adult Time (Social Policy Research
Centre Discussion Paper No. 137, February
2005).
[41] In 2000
there were 549,100 one-parent families in Australia. In 86% of these the parent
was female. See L Craig, above n 40,
8.
[42]
Victorian Railway Commissioners v Coultas (1888) 13 App Cas 222;
Hambrook v Stokes [1925] 1 KB 141; Chester v Waverley Corporation
[1939] HCA 25; (1939) 62 CLR 1 ; Bourhill v Young [1942] UKHL 5; [1943] AC 92;King v Phillips
[1953] 1 QB 429; McLoughlin v O’Brian [1982] UKHL 3; [1983] 1 AC
410.
[43] Barbara
Welke, in ‘Unreasonable Women: Gender and the Law of Accidental Injury
1970 – 1920’ (1994) Law and Social Inquiry 369 points to the
potentially problematic consequences for women that flow from what looks like,
and in some cases is, a beneficial attention
to gender on these early personal
injury claims: “ ... because the law is premised on a narrow image of what
constituted ‘ladylike’
conduct and a debilitating image of
women’s nature, all this came at an immediate const to some women and a
long-term cost
to all women.” This problematic entrenching or, as Welke
puts it, reification of gender norms via case law is discussed in
greater detail
below in section
III.
[44] An
excellent overview of feminist theory in relation to tort law is by Joanne
Conaghan, ‘Tort Law and the Feminist Critique
of Reason’ in A
Bottomley (ed) Feminist Perspectives on the Foundational Subjects of Law,
Cavendish Press, 1996. An overview of the American Feminist scholarship in tort
law is offered by Leslie Bender ‘An Overview
of Feminist Torts
Scholarship’ (1993) 78 Cornell Law Review 575. Joanne Conaghan
revisits the broad and varied nature of feminist analysis of many of the
foundational concepts of tort law in “Tort
Law and Feminist
Critique” (2003) 56 Current Legal Problems 175, a response to Gary
Schwartz’s article, “Feminist Approaches to Tort Law” (2001) 2
Theoretical Enquiries in Law
175. A more general consideration of feminist legal
theory is offered by Graycar and Morgan, The Hidden Gender of Law,
2nd ed, Federation Press, 2002.
[45] For example,
R Graycar, ‘Damaged Awards: the vicissitudes of life as a woman’
(1995) 3 Torts Law Journal 160; ‘Women’s Work: Who
Cares?’ (1992) 14 Sydney Law Review
70.
[46] L Bender,
‘A Lawyer’s Primer on Feminist Theory and Tort ‘ (1998) 38
Journal of Legal Education 3; L Finley ‘A Break in the Silence:
Including Women’s Issues in a Torts Course’ (1989) 1 Yale
Journal of Law and Feminism 41; Caroline Forell, ‘Essentialism,
Empathy and the Reasonable Woman’ (1994) 4 University of Illinois Law
Review 769; H Allen ‘One Law for all Reasonable Persons?’ (1988)
16 International Journal Soc L 419; R Martin, ‘A Feminist View of
the Reasonable Man: an alternative approach to liability in negligence for
personal injury’
(1994) Anglo-American Law Review 334; W Parker,
‘The Reasonable Person: a Gendered Concept?’ (1993) 23 Vic U
Wellington Law Review
105.
[47] C A
Goodzeit ‘Rethinking Emotional Distress law: Prenatal Malpractice and
Feminist Theory’ (1994) 63 Fordham Law Review 175; E. Handsley
‘Mental Injury Occasioned by Harm to Another: a Feminist Critique’
(1996) 14 Law and Inequality: a journal of theory and practice
391.
[48] See,
for example, Carol Pateman The Sexual Contract; Carol Smart Feminism
and the Power of Law; C MacKinnon ‘Feminism, Marxism, Method and the
State: toward Feminist Jurisprudence’ (1983) 7 (3) Signs
635.
[49]For
example, Genevieve Lloyd The Man of Reason: ‘Male’ and
‘Female’ in Western Philosophy, Methuen, London,
1984.
[50]
[1932] AC 562 ; see also Kavanagh v Akhtar [1998] NSWSC 779; (1998) 45 NSWLR 588;
Nader v Urban Transit Authority of NSW (1985) 2 NSWLR 501;
Commonwealth v McLean (1996) 41 NSWLR 389 and many
others.
[51]
Victorian Railways Commissioners v Coultas (1888) 13 App Cas 222. The
Privy council held that Mrs Coultas’ ‘severe nervous shock’
caused by her terror when a negligent railway crossing
gatekeeper allowed her
buggy onto the track so that a collision with a train was only narrowly avoided
was too remote from the gatekeeper’s
wrong.
[52] There
is a small number of cases where compensation has been given for psychiatric
harm caused by property damage, but this paper
does not consider them, largely
because they are relatively few. See Attia v British Gas Plc [1987] EWCA Civ 8; [1988] QB
304 and Campbelltown City Council v Mackay (1988) 15 NSWLR 501, which
take different
approaches.
[53] E
Shorter, A History of Psychiatry John Wiley & Sons, Inc, New York,
1997 , (hereafter, ‘Shorter’) p 116 ; Hare, Edward
“The History of ‘Nervous Disorders’ from 1600 to 1840, and a
Comparison with Modern Views” (1991)
159 British Journal of
Psychiatry 37 –
45.
[54] M
Foucault, Madness and civilisation, Random House, 1965, p
140.
[55] See n 16
above.
[56] For
example, in Coultas the court accepted physical harm (the miscarriage)
as evidence of the psychiatric harm’s
existence
[57] G
Mendelson ‘Posttraumatic Stress Disorder as Psychiatric Injury in Civil
Litigation’ (1995) 2(1) Psychiatry, Psychology and Law
53
[58]
(1888) 13 App Cas 222. In Victorian Railway Commissioners v
Coultas [1886] VicLawRp 182; (1886) 12 VLR 895 the railway gatekeeper had invited the
plaintiffs to cross a level crossing as the train was about to appear and a
collision was narrowly
avoided. Mrs Coultas suffered from a range of symptoms as
a consequence of her fright, including shock, a miscarriage and physical
injury.
The medical evidence agreed that she suffered from "nervous shock". A jury
awarded her damages and the defendant’s
appeal was rejected by the Full
Court of the Supreme Court of Victoria. However, the Privy Council held that she
could not recover
because this would be too much of an extension of liability.
[59] The history
of the rules used in the United States to bolster concerns about the imaginary
or unreal nature of psychiatric harm and
its gendered effect is considered in
the now classic article by Chamallas and Kerber ,’Women, Mothers and the
Law of Fright:
a History’ (1990) 88 Michigan L R
814.
[60] [1901] EWHC KB 1; [1901] 2
KB 669.
[61] The
zone of danger approach has remained influential in the United States in some
jurisdictions, although in California and other
states it is no longer a
requirement.
[62]
[1925] 1 KB
141.
[63] [1942] UKHL 5; [1943] AC
92.
[64] [1953] 1
QB 429.
[65]
Chamallas and Kerber at 848, quoting W Smith and H Solomon ‘Traumatic
Neuroses in Court’ (1943) 30 Va L Rev
193.
[66] [1939] HCA 25; (1939)
62 CLR 1.
[67] Law
Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) act 1944 (NSW) and its equivalents. Now
overtaken by the Civil Liability Act 2002
(NSW).
[68]
Shorter, above n 53,
145.
[69] At the
same time there also developed an anti-psychiatry movement, some of whom argued
that mental illness was a cultural construct;
that psychiatric illness was a
myth, see R D Laing, The Divided Self, 1960; Michel Foucault,
Madness and Civilisation, 1959; Thomas Szasz , The Myth of
Mental Illness,1961; Erving Goffman, Asylums
1961.
[70] Prosser,
Torts, 4th ed 1971 p 276, quoted in
McLoughlin v O’Brian [1981] 1 AC 410 at p
421.
[71]
DSM-III, Washington DC, American Psychiatry Association, 1980; DSM
III-R, 1987; DSM-IV, 1994; DSM-IV-TR,
2000.
[72] World
Health Organisation, The ICD-10 Classificaton of Mental and Behavioural
Disorders – clinical descriptions and diagnostic guidelines,
1992.
[73] See D
Butler ‘Identifying the compensable damage in “nervous shock”
cases’ (1997) 5(1) Torts Law Journal
67.
[74] [1861] EngR 822; (1861) 9
HL Cas 576; 11 ER
854.
[75] Descartes
first set up this separation between body and mind, drawing to some extent on
Christianity’s separation of body and
soul: Descartes, Meditation
VI.
[76] [1970] HCA 60; (1970)
125 CLR 383
[77]
This was so as early as 1911 in Coyle v John Watson Ltd [1915] AC 1 per
Lord Shaw at 14; Bourhill v Young [1942] UKHL 5; [1943] AC 92 at 103 per Lord Macmillan
at 103: ‘The distinction between mental shock and bodily injury was never
a scientific one...’;
see also R v Miller [1954] 2 QB 282; Mt
Isa Mines v Pusey [1970] HCA 60; (1970) 125 CLR 383 and Aboushadi v CIC Insurance
(1996) Aust Torts Reps 81-384 per Handley JA at 63,339. And Gummow
and Kirby JJ in Tame v NSW; Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd [2002]
HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317 at 378 observe, ‘Advances in the capacity of
medicine objectively to distinguish the genuine from the spurious, and renewed
attention to the need to establish breach, causation and a recogniseable
psychiatric that is not too remote, indicate the need for
re-accommodation of
the competing interests which are in play in “nervous shock”
cases.’
[78] See, for
example, Pratt & Goldsmith v Pratt [1975] VicRp 37; [1975] VR 378 where the mother
was refused compensation for nervous shock incurred after some weeks or months
of caring for her catastrophically
brain damaged daughter who had been made
that way by a car
accident.
[79]
Shock is no longer regarded by psychiatrists as necessary for all psychiatric
injuries. It does continue to be noted in DSM-IV80 as a
stressor for Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder, but not for other illnesses. There
is nothing about sudden sensory perception that
is necessarily connected to all
the possible definitions of psychiatric harm which are accepted in the manuals
we use such as DSM-IV.
It may be required for post traumatic stress disorder,
but it is certainly not necessary for psychotic depression, for
example.
[81]
Alcock v Chief Constable of South Yorkshire [1991] UKHL 5; [1992] 1 AC 310 per Lord
Keith at 398; Lord Ackner at 400; Lord Oliver at
411.
[82] See D
Butler ‘Nervous Shock at Common Law and Third Party Communications’
(1996) 4(2) Torts Law Journal 120 and ‘A Kind of Damage’
(1997) 5(2) Torts Law Journal 255. Clearly Brennan J in
Jaensch v Coffey [1984] HCA 52; (1984) 155 CLR 549 thought so, but Deane J, while
recognising that that was the orthodox position, left some leeway, and Gibbs CJ
left it open. Murphy
J did not discuss it (per Brennan J at 565 ; Deane J at 608
; Gibbs CJ at 555).
.
[83] For example,
in Coates v GIO (1995) 36 NSWLR 1 where there was merely the
passing of information to two children that their father had been killed in a
car accident, Kirby P in dissent, regarded the significance of the
information to the hearer as more important than the mode of discovery. He
argued
that advances in psychiatry were a reason to dispense with this
requirement, noting that the rules about perception reflected nineteenth
century
views about psychology and nineteenth century ways of communicating. Kirby
P’s lead was followed by the District Court
of NSW in Quayle v NSW
(1995) Aust Torts Rep 81-367. Similarly Lee J in Reeve v Brisbane City
Council [1995] 2 Qd R 661 regarded actual perception as not necessary for
liability. The plaintiff did not see the body of her dead husband for some days
after
she was informed of the accident at work in which he was killed. She did
not go to the scene, and only saw him at the funeral parlour
some days later. In
Petrie v Dowling [1992] 1 Qd R 284 the plaintiff was informed that her
daughter had been in an accident. At the hospital she tried to make light of it
and said to the
Sister ‘She isn’t dead, is she?’ The sister
replied ‘I’m afraid so.’ She was held able to recover
damages,
as actual perception of the accident was not required of her.
[84] D Butler
‘Nervous Shock at Common Law and Third Party Communications’ (1996)
4(2) Torts Law Journal 120 at
131.
[85] E
Handsley, ‘ Mental Injury Occasioned by Harm to Another: a Feminist
Critique’, (1996) 14 Law and Inequality 391-487 at 465, n
323.
[86] The
Australian Bureau of Statistics Breakdown of the 2006 Census showed an increase
in non-family households from 22.7% in 1996 to
28.3% in 2006.
http://abs.gov.au/ausstats/subscriber.nsf/LookupAttach/2070.0Publication29.01.096/$File/20700_Population_overview.pdf
[87]
E Handsley, ‘ Mental Injury occasioned by harm to another: a feminist
critique’, (1996) 14 Law and Inequality 391-487 at 465 n
323
[88] Tame v
NSW;Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317
at 383. See nn
21-23.
[89]
Politics, Bk I, xii,
1259a37
[90] See
for example, L M Antony and C Witts (eds), A Mind of One’s Own:
feminist essays on reason and objectivity, Westview Press, Boulder, 1993,
and S Harding and M Hintikka (eds) Discovering Reality: feminist perspectives
on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology and philosophy of science, D
Reidel publishing, Dordrecht,
1983.
[91]
See, for example, Genevieve Lloyd, The man of reason: ‘male’
and ‘female’ in Western Philosophy, Methuen, London,
1984
[92] For
example, in In re Edith Haynes [1904] 4 WAR 209, the female
applicant’s application to do the examination to become a legal
practitioner in Western Australia was refused on
the grounds that the word
‘person’ in the Legal Practitioners Act 1893 did not include women;
that the universal word
‘person’ in fact meant ‘man.’
The various Acts Interpretation Acts of the Australian jurisdictions have
now established that the word ‘person’ does include women, but the
need for such
legislation establishes the falsity of the claim of the law to be
at all times universal, neutral and unbiased in its
application.
[93]
See, for example, P Suber, ‘Legal Reasoning after Post-modern Critiques of
Reason’ (1997) 3 Legal Writing
21.
[94] Blyth
v Birmingham Waterworks Co [1856] EngR 223; (1856) 11 Ex 781 at 784; 156 ER 1047 per
Alderson B.
[95]
Vaughan v Menlove ([1837] EngR 424; 1837) 3 Bing NC
468.
[96]
Glasgow Corporation v Muir [1943] UKHL 2; [1943] AC 448 per Lord Macmillan at
457.
[97] Hall v
Brooklands Club (1933) 1 KB 205 per Greer LJ at
224.
[98]
Papatonakis v The Australian Telecommunications Commission & Anor
[1985] HCA 3; (1985) 156 CLR 7 per Deane J at
36.
[99] Elizabeth
Groscz, ‘Philosophy’ in Gunew (ed) Feminist Knowledge, Critique
and Construct, 1990. Quoted in R Martyn, ‘A Feminist View of the
Reasonable Man: an Alternative Approach to Liability in Negligence for
Personal
Injury’, (1994) Anglo-American Law Review 334. Also see above n
2.
[100][1942] UKHL 5; [1943] AC
92.
[101] At p
117.
[102] [1939]
HCA 25; (1939) 62 CLR
1.
[103] [1984] HCA 52; (1984)
155 CLR 549
[104]
[1984] HCA 52; (1984) 155 CLR 549 at
556
[105] ( at
568- 569)
[106]
[1984] HCA 52; (1984) 155 CLR 549 at
568-569.
[107]
Tame v NSW;Annetts v Australian Stations Pty Ltd [2002] HCA 35; (2002)
211 CLR
317.
[108]
Heuristic thought involves characteristically human leaps, rules of thumb etc
and can be contrasted with the way a computer reasons,
algorithmically,
step-by-step. See for example Patrick Suppes, ‘Heuristics and the
Axiomatic Method’ in R Groner,
M Groner and W Bischof Methods of
Heuristics Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, New Jersey, 1983 at 82
and Dietrich Dorner, ‘Heuristics and Cognition in Complex
systems’
in R Groner, M Groner and W Bischof (eds), above at 89; Leeanne Sharp
‘Cognitive Heuristics and the Law: an
Interdisciplinary Approach to Better
Judicial Decision-making ‘ (1995) 20 Bulletin of the Australian Society
of Legal Philosophy 71,
86.
[109] See,
for example, James Boyle, ‘The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory
and Local Social Thought’ (1985) 133(4) University of Pennsylvania Law
Review 685; Roberto Unger, Knowledge and Politics, Collier
Macmillan, New York, 1975; Peter Goodrich, Legal Discourse , St
Martins Press, New York, 1987 and the huge feminist literature on the subject,
including Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice, Harvard University
Press, 1982; Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (eds) Discovering Reality:
Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology and Philosophy
of Science, D Reidel, Dordrecht, 1983.
[110] At
[105].
[111]
Sexual divisions in Law, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London, 1985, p
3
[112] That
view was overturned in Australia in R v L [1991] HCA 48; (1991) 103 ALR
577.
[113] Sir
William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England in Fourteen
Books, 4th ed., ed T Cooley, Callahan & Co,
Chicago, 1899, v 1 p
31.
[114]27 UK
1882; New South Wales 1879 (42 Vict No 11); Victoria 1884 (48 Vict No 828);
Queensland 1890 (54 Vict No 9); South Australia
(then including the
Northern Territory) 1884 (46 and 47 Vict No 300); Western Australia 1982 (55
Vict No 20); Tasmania 1935 (26 Geo
V No 90); what is now the Australian Capital
Territory was then part of New South
Wales.
[115] J
Morgan ‘Sexual Harassment and the Public/Private Dichotomy’ M
Thornton (ed), Public and Private:Feminist Legal Debates, Oxford
University Press, Melbourne 1995 at
96.
[116]
‘The Cartography of Public and Private’ in Margaret Thornton (ed)
Public and Private: Feminist Legal Debates, Oxford University Press, 1995
at13
[117]
Annetts v Australia Stations at
308.
[118] [1942] UKHL 5; [1943]
AC 92.
[119]
[1925] 1 KB 141 at
151.
[120]
‘Women, Mothers and the Law of Fright: a History’ (1990) 88
Michigan Law Review
814.
[121] For
example, King v Phillips [1953] 1 QB 429; Hambrook v Stokes
Bros [1925] 1 KB 141 ; Storm v Geeves [1965] TASStRp 22; [1965] Tas SR 252;
Hinz v Berry [1970] 2 QB
40.
[122] See M
Whitford, ‘Luce Iragaray’s Critique of Rationality’ in M
Griffiths and M Whitford Feminist Perspectives in Philosophy, Macmillan,
London, 1988, discussed in Genevieve Lloyd, ‘Maleness, Metaphor and the
Crisis of Reason’ in L Antony and
C Witt (eds), A Mind of One’s
Own, Westview Press, Boulder,
1993.
[123] Carol
Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s
Development, Harvard University Press, 1982.
[124] C
Mackinnon, Feminism Unmodified, Harvard University Press,
1987.
[125] L
Bender, ‘Changing the Values in Tort Law‘ (1990) Tulsa LJ
759
[126] Barbara
Ann Hocking and Alison Smith ‘From Coultas to Alcock and
Beyond: will Tort Law Fail Women?’ [1995] QUTLawJl 8; (1995) 11 Queensland University of
Technology Law Journal
120.
[127] (1989)
Aust TR 80-263
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UNSWLRS/2010/45.html