Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
CRIMINALISATION: APPLYING A LIVING-STANDARD
ANALYSIS TO NON-CONSENSUAL PHOTOGRAPHY AND
DISTRIBUTION
KELLEY BURTON [*]
Determining whether conduct should be criminalised or
not, is a serious problem because the criminal law is becoming more civilised.
This article explores the living-standard analysis tool, which provides a
systematic decision-making framework rather than leaving
it to intuition. This
tool is applied to four examples of non-consensual photography and distribution,
and the results are compared
with the criminal law. This comparison indicates
that the two do not always coincide. Over-criminalisation is one possible
explanation
for this discrepancy. This article recommends further research into
the usefulness of the living-standard analysis tool.
I INTRODUCTION
Determining the boundaries of criminal law is a serious problem. There is a trend of criminal law encroaching upon conduct that was ‘previously thought to be civil or regulatory in character’.[1] The criminal law has been described as a ‘predominantly administrative system managing enormous numbers of relatively non-serious and “regulatory offences”’.[2]
Most commentators suggest that there is no unifying factor that underpins the decision to criminalise conduct. For example, Simester and Sullivan conclude that ‘the sheer variety of conduct that has been designated a criminal wrong defies reduction to any “essential” minimum’.[3] Similarly, Findlay, Odgers and Yeo say that there is no simple explanation about why the criminal law has pursued one direction and not another.[4] Further, Ashworth suggests that the criminal law is ‘unprincipled and chaotic’ and questions whether the criminal law is a ‘lost cause’.[5]
Arguably, the development of criminal law has been unpredictable because of
a ‘fundamental ambiguity of its central organising
principles’.[6] Several
policies or principles may be selected during a value laden selection process to
justify criminalisation.[7] In any
event, the boundaries of criminal law are based on rationality and justice and
not merely chance or contingency.[8]
Whether non-consensual photography and distribution falls within the
boundaries of criminal law is a live issue. In this article
I have chosen
non-consensual photography and distribution over other examples of criminal
conduct because it is topical in the 21st
century.[9] Many jurisdictions have
provided a legislative response to this conduct in the 21st
century.[10] Further, recent media
reports (some of which are discussed below) are littered with examples of this
conduct, and it has been said
that the community is outraged by such
conduct.[11]
While non-consensual photography is not a new phenomenon, the means of
photographing and distributing such photographs have become
more sophisticated
with the advent of digital
cameras,[12]
mobile phone cameras, video cameras, web cams and the Internet. To
determine whether these examples of non-consensual photography
and distribution
should be criminalised, this article will apply a living-standard analysis.
von Hirsch and Jareborg created the living-standard analysis tool, which
gauged the seriousness of criminal
harm.[13]
Their approach is normative because it indicates how offences
‘should’ be rated.[14]
They restricted themselves to conduct that was already criminalised, for
example, homicide, assault, battery, petty assault, armed
robbery, forcible
rape, date rape, burglary with ransacking, common residential burglary and auto
theft because they were interested
in sentencing
policy.[15]
However, they recognised that the living-standard analysis could be
employed to determine whether conduct should be
criminalised.[16] None of the
literature attempts to apply the living-standard analysis tool to determine
whether conduct should be criminalised.
Thus, in this article I will fill a gap
in the literature by applying the living-standard analysis tool to determine
whether non-consensual
photography and distribution should be criminalised or
not.
In this article I will conclude with a comparison between the
results of the living-standard analysis tool and the black letter law
pertaining
to non-consensual photography and distribution.
II EXAMPLES OF NON-CONSENSUAL PHOTOGRAPHY AND DISTRIBUTION
Non-consensual photography and distribution is not a new phenomenon. In 1890, Warren and Brandeis anticipated the need to protect privacy from people that make surreptitious and instantaneous photographs.[17]
More explicitly, the literature approximately 100 years later discusses an incident where a female, who was leaving a funhouse with her two children, was photographed when an air jet unexpectedly blew her skirt up in the air, such that her underwear was visible in the photograph.[18]
The photographer published the photograph on the front page of a newspaper.
As a result of this, the female was ‘embarrassed,
self-conscious,
upset...was known to cry on
occasions’[19]
and brought an action on the basis that her privacy had been invaded. The
Alabama Supreme Court concluded that the female had a
reasonable expectation of
privacy in the circumstances because the intrusion was indecent, vulgar,
embarrassing and without the female’s
volition.[20] This incident
occurred in the 1960s, but numerous incidents of non-consensual photography and
distribution have been reported beyond
2000.
The Australian Standing
Committee of Attorneys-General highlights several prominent instances of
photographing and distributing non-consensual
photographs in its Discussion
Paper.[21]
One of these instances involved photographing children at South Bank Parklands in Brisbane without the knowledge or permission of their parents.[22] When the children were covertly photographed, they were dressed in swimmers and playing in a public park. The images were brought to the media’s attention when they were uploaded on a website. The website had no links to pornography or paedophilia, but the author of the website removed the website after media exposure. At the time of the incident, the conduct was not criminalised in Queensland, but the media claimed the community was outraged by such conduct.[23]
However, the media did not support their claim with any evidence, especially not empirical evidence. Further instances discussed in the Australian Standing Committee of Attorneys-General Discussion Paper include covertly photographing Melbourne school boys dressed in half of their rowing suits,[24] and a 16 year old surf lifesaver.[25]
Similar instances have occurred outside Australia, for example, in New Zealand, a man filmed school girls walking along a public street, through a gap in a curtain in a bus parked on a public street.[26]
In these examples, there was no pre-existing relationship between the
person taking the photograph and the subject. Further, although
the subjects in
these instances were children, children are not the only subjects of
non-consensual photographs.
Several incidents of covert filming targeted
females doing every day activities in places that may be accessed by the public.
For
example, photographing topless female bathers at a public
beach,[27]
photographing up the skirts of females while they are in shopping
malls,[28]
and covertly photographing a female dressed in outer clothing sitting on a
step outside a Canadian building and subsequently publishing
it in a
magazine.[29]
In contrast to these instances involving places accessible by the public, other instances have involved more private settings and more embarrassing circumstances. In particular, the 2004 New Zealand Law Commission Study Paper highlights incidents such as covertly filming teenage girls undressing in their bedroom, filming boys undressing using a hand-held camera behind a one-way window, installing a camera in a dressing room to film female performers, filming a woman trying on a swimsuit at a market changing booth, filming women using a tanning salon, filming cheerleaders undressing using a video camera behind a two-way mirror and filming females as they used the home bathroom of the person making the visual recording.[30]
Similar incidents have been reported in Canada, including a man who filmed his female colleagues using a co-ed washroom;[31] a man who videotaped his consensual sexual activities with a female, but who showed them to his friends at a party without the female’s consent;[32] and a landlord who installed a video camera in the air vent of a rental apartment tenanted by a female.[33] This last Canadian incident is analogous to incidents in the United Kingdom where landlords fixed spyholes into bathrooms;[34] in New South Wales where a man filmed his female flatmates whilst they were showering;[35] and in Queensland where a stepfather filmed his adult stepdaughters showering.[36]
Another intimate example involved a man peeping through a bedroom window and photographing a female while she was sleeping.[37]
In most of these examples, there was a pre-existing relationship between
the person making the non-consensual visual recording and
the subject, but this
is not always the case.
This article suggests that the key non-consensual
photography incidents emerging out of the media reports and the discussion
papers
involve photographing a child playing in a public park, photographing a
topless female bather at a public beach, up-skirt filming
at a shopping centre
and photographing a housemate as they shower in the bathroom. This article will
determine whether these incidents
should be criminalised by applying the
living-standard analysis tool. The next section of this article outlines the
living-standard
analysis tool.
III LIVING-STANDARD ANALYSIS TOOL
The von Hirsch-Jareborg living-standard analysis tool has merit because it provides a systematic framework for determining whether conduct should be criminalised or not, rather than making the decision intuitively, impressionistically or ‘on the basis of traditional assumptions about the ranking of offences. The von Hirsch-Jareborg approach urges one to dig deeper, and to look more closely at the interests affected’.[38]
Under the von Hirsch-Jareborg schema, there are four generic-interest dimensions that may be affected by a crime, that is, ‘physical integrity, material support and amenity, freedom from humiliation, and privacy and autonomy’.[39]
Physical integrity ‘embraces health, safety, and avoidance of
physical pain’.[40] Material
support and amenity includes all types of material interests, for example, food,
shelter and luxuries.[41] Freedom
from humiliation encompasses ‘injuries to self-respect that derive from
others’
mistreatment’.[42] Privacy
and autonomy ‘promotes
self-respect’[43] and helps a
person to pursue various
preferences.[44] While the list of
generic-interest dimensions appears compelling, a decision-maker should be aware
of its weaknesses. It is conceded
that one of the weaknesses with the von
Hirsch-Jareborg living-standard tool is that the list of generic-interest
dimensions is random,
incomplete and not based on theory. The list of
generic-interest dimensions is based on von Hirsch and Jareborg’s
impressions
of legally protected interests usually involved in victimising
crimes.[45] Despite this weakness,
the living-standard analysis tool gives credence to a broad range of interests
that may be overlooked had
the decision to criminalise conduct been made
intuitively.
The next step in the von Hirsch-Jareborg living-standard
analysis tool is to estimate the degree to which the living standard of a
typical victim would be affected in a typical
case.[46] In this way, they support
a ‘standard harm’ rather than dealing with victims that are
particularly vulnerable or
resilient.[47] The living standard
does not focus on an ‘actual life quality or goal achievement, but on the
means or capabilities for achieving a certain quality of life. It
is also standardized, referring to the means and capabilities that would
ordinarily help one achieve a good
life’.[48] Consequently, the
living standard can be employed without knowing a person’s focal aims or
goals.[49] Thus, living-standards
differ from welfare interests because the former is not based on a choice
criterion.[50] von Hirsch and
Jareborg grade an intrusion into a person’s living-standard at one of four
levels in descending order as set
out in the table
below.[51] Four levels were chosen
because the difference between them was reasonably easy to
discern.[52] A larger number of
levels, for example, 100, would have given a deceptive sense of
precision.
Level
|
Category
|
General Description
|
1ْ
|
Subsistence
|
Survival, but with maintenance of no more than elementary human capacities
to function. No satisfactions presupposed at this level.
|
2ْ
|
Minimal well-being
|
Maintenance of a minimal level of comfort and dignity.
|
3ْ
|
Adequate well-being
|
Maintenance of an ‘adequate’ level of comfort and
dignity.
|
4ْ
|
Enhanced well-being
|
Significant enhancement in quality-of-life above the mere
‘adequate’ level.
|
The terms ‘subsistence’, ‘minimal well-being’,
‘adequate well-being’ and ‘enhanced well-being’
emerge
in the table above and are worthy of further exploration.
‘Subsistence’ ‘means barely getting by. Included
would be
preservation of one’s major physical and cognitive functions, and
preservation of a minimal capacity for social
functioning.’[53]
‘Minimal well-being’ provides a ‘minimum level of comfort and
dignity’.[54] While
‘minimal well-being’ offers a better standard of life than
‘subsistence’, it is still substandard.
‘Adequate
well-being’ refers to a level of comfort and dignity that is ‘not
leading a substandard or deprived
existence’.[55] Finally,
‘enhanced well-being’, is above an ‘adequate well-being’
and ‘addresses those concerns that
improves someone’s
quality-of-life
significantly’.[56]
Consequently, the quality-of-life improves from levels
1ْ to
4ْ .
Whether a level
1ْ to
4ْ is attributed to the
conduct, depends on the temporal perspective taken. von Hirsch and Jareborg
adopt a one-year or slightly longer
temporal
perspective.[57] This means that
the relevant question in assessing the conduct is ‘How has your year
been?’[58] rather than
‘How was your day?’[59]
or ‘How was your last
decade?’.[60] It is asserted
that these latter two expressions overrate or underrate the conduct.
To
link the levels in the table above with the generic-interest dimensions
identified above, von Hirsch and Jareborg assert that physical
integrity and
material support and amenity may relate to all four levels in the table
above.[61] In contrast, freedom
from humiliation, and privacy and autonomy develop at levels
2ْ to
4ْ in the table
above.[62] The reason for this is
that level 1ْ relates to
survival, and a person may survive without privacy or
humiliation.[63] After determining
the relevant level in the table above, the next step is to map the level onto a
harm gradation scale.[64] The von
Hirsch and Jareborg harm gradation table is set out
below.[65]
Harm Gradation
|
Living-Standard Level Intruded Upon
|
I – grave
|
Subsistence (living-standard level
1ْ)
|
II – serious
|
Minimal well-being (level
2ْ)
|
III – upper-intermediate
|
Adequate well-being (level
3ْ)
|
IV – lower-intermediate
|
Enhanced well-being (level
4ْ)
|
V – lesser
|
Living standard not affected or only marginally so
|
von Hirsch and Jareborg acknowledge that their living-standard analysis tool is not precise and requires judgment.[66] They retreat on the issue of criminalisation by asserting that if a type of conduct constitutes grave harmfulness on the harm gradation table above, it ‘does not necessarily settle whether it should be proscribed’.[67] In addition to considering harmfulness, they recommend that the legislature consider other factors in making the decision to criminalise conduct, for example, the social value of the conduct, the ability to enforce the criminal law and the impact the prohibition has on individual autonomy and privacy.[68] They do not explore these factors and focus their discussion on harmfulness. Similarly, in this article I will concentrate on the living-standard analysis tool, and thus harmfulness. A discussion of these other factors is beyond the scope of this article. The living-standard analysis tool provides a systematic conceptual framework for gauging criminal harm rather than leaving it to guesswork.[69] Ashworth described the living-standard analysis tool as ‘pathbreaking’.[70]
While the living-standard analysis tool has not been applied in later
sentencing literature or applied in making the decision to
criminalise conduct,
this article will fill this gap. In particular, in this article I will proceed
to apply the living-standard
analysis tool to four examples of non-consensual
photography and distribution to determine whether the examples should be
criminalised.
IV APPLICATION OF THE LIVING-STANDARD ANALYSIS TOOL TO EXAMPLES OF NON-CONSENSUAL PHOTOGRAPHY AND DISTRIBUTION
In this article I will apply the living-standard analysis tool to four
examples of non-consensual photography. The four examples
are: (1)
photographing a child playing in a public park; (2) photographing a topless
female bather at a public beach; (3) up-skirt
filming at a shopping centre; and
(4) photographing a housemate as they shower in the bathroom. I argue that,
intuitively, photographing
a housemate as they shower in the bathroom and
up-skirt filming at a shopping centre, involve a greater intrusion on
privacy[71]
(and thus more harm and a greater impact on a person’s living
standard) than photographing a child playing in a public park
or photographing a
topless female bather at a public beach. Consequently, my intuition suggests
that if any of these examples should
be criminalised, it should be photographing
a housemate as they shower in the bathroom and up-skirt filming at a shopping
centre.
In any event, the living-standard analysis tool is more sophisticated
than merely my intuition and it will be applied to each of
these four
examples.
In the first example of photographing a child playing in a
public park, the relevant interest dimensions are freedom from humiliation,
and
privacy and autonomy. This article focuses on examples of non-consensual
photography and this example assumes that the child
and their parents (or
guardian) do not expressly consent to the photography. It also assumes that
child has not impliedly consented
to the photography merely because they are in
a public place. The living-standard analysis tool does not distinguish child
victims
from adult victims. Physical integrity is not relevant in this example
from a one year temporal perspective. Note that this conclusion
on physical
integrity does not cover other types of conduct that may follow on from taking a
photograph of a child, for example,
kidnapping, torture, sexual assault or rape.
This conclusion on physical integrity in this example is consistent with von
Hirsch
and Jareborg’s example of assault. More specifically, they assert
that in an assault where the victim sustained substantial
bruises and
lacerations, but did not require hospitalisation, level
4ْ may not be justified from
a one-year temporal
perspective.[72]
Further, taking a photograph of a child playing in a public park does not
involve material interests and thus the material support
and amenity interest
dimension is not relevant. The freedom from humiliation and the privacy and
autonomy interest dimensions in
this example involve level
4ْ because a child’s
living-standard is not affected, from a one-year temporal perspective, if they
had their photograph taken
in a public place. This conclusion on the freedom
from humiliation interest dimension in this example is consistent with von
Hirsch
and Jareborg’s conclusion on forced rape and date rape, which
involved level 2ْ because it
is the norm in our culture that sexual acts are done with
consent.[73] Further, the
conclusion in this example on privacy and autonomy is consistent with von Hirsch
and Jareborg’s level 4ْ
attributed to a residential burglary where the home is not significantly
disturbed[74] and level
2ْ to a residential burglary
with ransacking.[75] Taking a
photograph of a child in a public place involves a lesser intrusion on privacy
than an intrusion in a private place, such
as a home, and thus the level
attributed to this example cannot be more than level
4ْ. In summary, the
living-standard analysis tool indicates that photographing a child playing in a
public park results in an intrusion
affecting enhanced well-being, that is,
level 4ْ.
The same
conclusion will be reached with respect to the second example, which is
photographing a topless female bather at a public
beach. The living-standard
analysis tool does not distinguish victims on the basis of gender. Similarly,
to the child photograph
discussed above, this example of the topless female
bather assumes that the female has not expressly consented to the photography
or
impliedly consented merely because she was in a public place. For the same
reasons as the example above, the physical integrity
and the material support
and amenity interest dimension are irrelevant. Note that the conclusion on
physical integrity does not
canvass further conduct, where the photographer may
stalk, sexually assault or rape the topless female bather. Photographing a
topless
female bather in a public place involves a lesser intrusion on privacy
than the home invasions provided by von Hirsch and Jareborg,
and mentioned
above. Consequently, level
4ْ should be attributed to
privacy and autonomy. A couple of arguments could be made with regard to
humiliation. One argument is that
if a female chooses to bath topless at a
public beach, she would not be humiliated by another person observing or
photographing her.
An alternative argument is that the topless female bather is
content for surrounding people to observe her, but may not be content
with the
surrounding people making a permanent record of her in that state. In any
event, it is plausible that taking a photograph
of a topless female bather at a
public beach will only affect the female’s enhanced well-being and thus be
a level 4ْ.
The third
example considered in this article is up-skirt filming at a shopping centre. As
the living-standard analysis tool only
applies to conduct where there is an
identifiable victim,[76]
this article assumes that the subject of the up-skirt filming is
identifiable. This is possible when the subject has a ‘distinguishing
tattoo, piercing or
birthmark’.[77]
For the same reasons as discussed in examples one and two, the physical
integrity and material support and amenity interest dimensions
are irrelevant.
The privacy and autonomy and the humiliation interests dimension are rated at
level 4ْ as the photography
intrusion has affected the subject’s enhanced well-being. Attributing a
level 1ْ,
2ْ or
3ْ to up-skirt filming in a
shopping centre is implausible considering that the living-standard analysis
tool is used from a one-year
temporal perspective.
The fourth and final
example involves photographing a housemate showering in the bathroom. In this
example, the housemate has not
been made homeless and they have not lost any
material possessions. Thus, material support and amenity is not affected.
Similarly,
physical integrity is not affected, provided that the photographer
merely wants to photograph the housemate showering and does not
attempt to
engage in sexual assault or rape. This example intrudes on privacy and
autonomy. Arguably, it is more intrusive than
three examples above because it
occurs in a home. The photographer has entered a space in the house (bathroom)
uninvited and an
analogy may be made with a burglar who enters a house
uninvited. As mentioned above, von Hirsch and Jareborg rated the intrusion
on
privacy and autonomy in a residential burglary with no ransacking at level
4ْ. Similarly, the privacy
and autonomy intrusion in this example is level
4ْ. With regard to
humiliation, this example is more humiliating than examples one and two above,
but arguably equal to example three,
which also involves an intrusion into
private body parts, albeit that example three occurs in a shopping centre
(public place) and
example four occurs in a home bathroom (private place). Once
again, the one-year temporal perspective would not justify a level
1ْ,
2ْ or
3ْ for humiliation in this
example. As mentioned above, von Hirsch and Jareborg attributed level
2ْ to humiliation for forced
rape and date rape. Thus, it seems reasonable to award a much lower level, for
example, level 4ْ to a person
who photographs their housemate showering.
Arguably, a higher level of
harm would occur if the photographer in the four examples above went further
than merely taking the photograph,
and distributed it on the Internet to a world
wide audience. In such a case, the rating for freedom from humiliation, and the
privacy
and autonomy interest dimensions may increase from level
4ْ to level
3ْ or
2ْ . As mentioned above, the
freedom from humiliation, and privacy and autonomy interest dimensions cannot be
rated at 1ْ. These
additional levels (level 3ْ
or 2ْ ) include
upper-intermediate and serious harm on the harm gradation table. However, given
that the distribution on the Internet
is judged from a one-year temporal
perspective, a lower level is more appropriate.
As discussed above, the
living-standard analysis tool rated all four examples of non-consensual
photography at level 4ْ.
Presumably, it grouped the different types of non-consensual photography
together, because the tool was designed to deal with a
range of offences, for
example, homicide, armed robbery, burglary and date rape etc. Thus, the
living-standard analysis tool results
did not match my intuition as set out
above. In particular, I speculated that the last two examples (up-skirt filming
at a shopping
centre and photographing a housemate as they shower in the
bathroom) involved a greater intrusion into a person’s living-standard.
A
level 4ْ may be transferred
to the harm gradation table at either IV or V, which represent
lower-intermediate or lesser harms. von Hirsch
and Jareborg did not indicate
the point on the continuum (level
1ْ to
4ْ) at which criminalisation
of the conduct would be necessary. Arguably, where the conduct impacts on
subsistence and results in grave
harm, there is a stronger basis for
criminalising the conduct than where the conduct only marginally impacts on a
person’s
living-standard and results in a lesser harm. Consequently, the
application of the living-standard analysis tool concludes that
each of the four
photography examples are at the lowest point on the continuum, that is, level
4ْ . If a dividing line was
drawn across the four levels to separate conduct that should be criminalised
from conduct that should not
be criminalised, the four examples explored in this
article are more likely to fall on the side of the dividing line where conduct
should not be criminalised because they fall within level
4ْ. In such a case, the
living-standard analysis would not support the criminalisation of these four
examples of non-consensual photography
and the following discussion will proceed
on this basis.
V COMPARING THE RESULTS OF THE LIVING-STANDARD ANALYSIS TOOL WITH THE CRIMINAL LAW
The results from the living-standard analysis tool with respect to the
four examples of non-consensual photography above will be compared
to the
criminal laws in Queensland, New South Wales, New Zealand and Canada. Four
jurisdictions have been chosen to determine whether
there is a pattern in the
way the four examples of non-consensual photography are treated by the criminal
law. In relation to the
first example, that is, photographing a child playing
in a public park, it is not criminalised in Queensland, New South Wales, New
Zealand or Canada.[78]
Additionally, the second example of photographing a topless female bather at a
public beach is not criminalised in any of the four
jurisdictions.[79] For
completeness, if the photograph of the child playing in a public park or the
photograph of the topless female bather were distributed
through the Internet,
it would not be an offence in these four jurisdictions. As the first two
examples of non-consensual photography
are not criminalised in the four
jurisdictions, it follows that the criminal law (or lack of) is consistent with
the results of the
living-standard analysis tool, which indicated that the first
two examples should not be criminalised.
The criminalisation of the third
and fourth example of non-consensual photography is more controversial. As
discussed above, the
living-standard analysis tool suggested that up-skirt
filming should not be criminalised. This result is consistent with the criminal
law position in New South Wales and Canada, which do not criminalise
non-consensual up-skirt filming or the distribution of up-skirt
filming images
on the Internet.[80] However,
non-consensual up-skirt filming is criminalised in Queensland and New
Zealand.[81] Further, the
distribution of up-skirt filming images on the Internet is criminalised in
Queensland and New Zealand.[82]
This means that the results of the living-standard analysis tool for up-skirt
filming are not consistent with the criminal law position
in Queensland and New
Zealand. With regard to up-skirt filming, the comparison between the
living-standard analysis tool and the
black letter criminal law could illustrate
that (a) New South Wales and Canada have interpreted up-skirt filming in a
similar fashion
to the living-standard analysis tool, (b) Queensland and New
Zealand have over-criminalised with respect to up-skirt filming, (c)
drawing a
line across the four levels in the living-standard analysis tool and concluding
that if the conduct falls within level
4ْ , it should not be
criminalised, is flawed or (d) if it could be demonstrated that some types of
conduct that fall within level
4ْ should be criminalised, it
could follow that New South Wales and Canada have under-criminalised with
respect to up-skirt filming.
Similarly to example three, an inconsistency
arises with respect to non-consensual photography example four, which is
photographing
a housemate as they shower in the bathroom. As discussed above,
the living-standard analysis tool suggested that this example should
not be
criminalised. In contrast, Queensland, New South Wales, New Zealand and Canada
criminalise this example of
photography.[83] All of these
jurisdictions, barring New South Wales, also criminalise the distribution of
such photographs.[84] Once again,
the inconsistency between the criminal law and the results of the
living-standard analysis tool may be explained by
reasons similar to (a), (b),
(c) or (d) above.
VI CONCLUSION
Determining the boundaries of criminal law is a serious issue in an
environment where criminal law is becoming more civilised. The
living-standard
analysis tool provides a systematic framework for determining whether conduct
should be criminalised or not, rather
than leaving the decision to guesswork and
intuition.
The first two examples of non-consensual photography used in
this article, that is, photographing a child playing in a public park
and
photographing a topless female bather, demonstrated consistent results between
the criminal law in Queensland, New South Wales,
New Zealand and Canada, and the
living-standard analysis tool (drawing a line across at level
4ْ). Both the criminal law
and the living-standard analysis tool concluded that these two examples of
non-consensual photography should
not be criminalised. The outcome that can be
drawn from these two examples of non-consensual photography is that the
living-standard
analysis tool offers an explanation of what should not be
criminalised, which has been applied universally in these four
jurisdictions.
The third example of non-consensual photography, that is,
up-skirt filming, casts doubt on the living-standard analysis tool at an
explanatory level. Drawing a line across the living-standard analysis tool at
level 4ْ suggested that
up-skirt filming should not be criminalised. This is consistent with the
criminal law position in New South Wales
and Canada, but inconsistent with the
position in Queensland and New Zealand. In this article I put forward several
possible explanations
for the difference between the results of drawing a line
across the living-standard analysis tool at level
4ْ and the criminal law.
These are (a) some jurisdictions and the living-standard analysis tool have
interpreted the conduct similarly,
(b) some jurisdictions have over-criminalised
the conduct, (c) drawing a line across the four levels in the living-standard
analysis
tool and concluding that if the conduct falls within level
4ْ , it should not be
criminalised, is flawed or (d) if it could be demonstrated that some types of
conduct that fall within level
4ْ should be criminalised, it
could follow that some jurisdictions have under-criminalised the conduct.
Future research on criminalisation
may benefit from a closer examination of
where to draw the dividing line across the four levels to determine whether
conduct should
be criminalised or not. Further, if it is determined that some
types of conduct falling into level
4ْ should be criminalised,
while other types should not, criteria for separating these two categories needs
to be developed. Consequently,
the third example of non-consensual photography
demonstrates that living-standard analysis tool offers an explanation of what
should
not be criminalised, which has been applied by some jurisdictions.
The fourth example of non-consensual photography of photographing a
housemate showering in the bathroom, also demonstrated inconsistent
results
between the living-standard analysis tool and the criminal law. In particular,
drawing a line across the living-standard
analysis tool at level
4ْ concluded that
photographing a housemate showering in the bathroom should not be criminalised.
However, it is criminalised in all
four jurisdictions. This means that the
living-standard analysis tool offers an explanation of what should not be
criminalised,
which was exceeded by the criminal law in all four jurisdictions.
Consequently, the living-standard analysis tool may be viewed
‘neither as
ideal nor as explanation but rather as an ideological framework in terms of
which policy debate about criminal
law is
expressed’.[85]
As an ‘ideological
framework’,[86] it facilitates
legislative decision making in a criminal law context.
[*] BBus(Acc) LLB (Hons) GradDip LegalPrac LLM (QUT) PhD candidate (USQ); Lecturer, School of Law, QUT.
[1] J C Coffee, 'Paradigms Lost: The Blurring of the Criminal and Civil Law Models
- And What Can Be Done About It' (1992) 101 The Yale Law Journal 1875,
1875.
[2] L Farmer, 'The Obsession
with Definition' (1996) 5 Social and Legal Studies 57, 64-6.
[3] A P Simester and G R Sullivan,
Criminal Law Theory and Doctrine (Hart, 2nd ed, 2003) 3.
Further, McSherry and Naylor contend that: ‘the limits of the criminal law
cannot be set by reference
to a “simple principle”, be it harm,
individual liberty or whatever. Instead the boundaries of the law are shaped by
a variety of forces that operate as broad guidelines rather than its clear-cut
criteria’: B McSherry and B Naylor, Australian Criminal Laws: Critical
Perspectives (Oxford University Press, 2004) 22.
[4] M Findlay, S Odgers and S Yeo,
Australian Criminal Justice (Oxford University Press, 3rd ed,
2005) 12.
[5] A Ashworth, 'Is the
Criminal Law a Lost Cause?' (2000) 116 The Law Quarterly Review 225,
225.
[6]
Ibid.
[7] Findlay, Odgers and
Yeo, above n 4, 12.
[8]
Ibid.
[9] As mentioned below, the
living-standard analysis tool does not apply to victimless crimes. It only
applies where the victim is
identifiable. Thus, this article will consider
examples of non-consensual photography and distribution where the victim is
identifiable.
[10] For example
see Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) s 216G-N, which came into effect in December
2006; Criminal Code (Qld) s 227A-C, which came into effect in December
2005; Criminal Code (Can) s 162, which came into effect in November 2005;
Sexual Offences Act 2003 (UK) s 67, which came into effect in May 2004;
and Summary Offences Act 1988 (NSW) s 21G-H, which came into effect in
March 2004.
[11] Standing
Committee of Attorneys-General, Unauthorised Photographs on the Internet and
Ancillary Privacy Issues (2005) 9
<http://www.ag.gov.au>
at 1 October
2005.
[12] There is a trend to
embed small cameras in everyday objects, for example, teddy bears, clocks, smoke
detectors, exit signs and pens:
C Calvert and J Brown, 'Video Voyeurism,
Privacy, and the Internet: Exposing Peeping Toms in Cyberspace' (2000) 18
Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law Journal 469,
480.
[13] A von Hirsch and N
Jareborg, 'Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living-Standard Analysis' (1991) 11
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1. See also M Treip, 'Re-Thinking the
Study of Criminal Law?' (1992) 55 The Modern Law Review 733. The
definition of ‘living standard’ used in this work is much broader
than that used by economists. It refers to ‘the
degree of economic
affluence or want...[and] non-economic capabilities that affect personal
well-being’: A von Hirsch and N
Jareborg, 'Gauging Criminal Harm: A
Living-Standard Analysis' (1991) 11 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1,
7.
[14] von Hirsch and Jareborg,
above n 13, 6.
[15] von Hirsch
and Jareborg, above n 13, 3 and
24-8.
[16]
Ibid.
[17] S Warren and L
Brandeis, 'The Right to Privacy' (1890) IV Harvard Law Review 193, 195
and 211.
[18] A McClurg,
'Bringing Privacy Law Out of the Closet: A Tort Theory of Liability for
Intrusions in Public Places' (1995) 73 North Carolina Law Review 989,
1045; L Rothenberg, 'Re-thinking Privacy: Peeping Toms, Video Voyeurs, and the
Failure of Criminal Law to Recognize a Reasonable
Expectation of Privacy in the
Public Space' (1999-2000) 49 American University Law Review 1127, 1148;
and Calvert and Brown, above n 12,
490.
[19] Calvert and Brown,
above n 12, 490.
[20] Daily
Times Democrat v Graham 276 Ala 380 (1964). Note that this is a civil case
and not a criminal case.
[21]
Standing Committee of Attorneys-General, above n 11, 5-6.
[22] Ibid. See further:
‘Parents Warned over Online Beach Photos’, The Age
(Melbourne), 27 January
2005.
[23] Standing Committee of
Attorneys-General, above n 11, 12.
[24] Ibid 5. See further:
‘Vic-Police Powerless to Act on Gay Website Containing Schoolboys’,
Australian Associated Press (Australia), 22 February
2002.
[25] Standing Committee of
Attorneys-General, above n 11,
5.
[26] New Zealand Law
Commission, Intimate Covert Filming Study Paper (2004) 41
<http://www.lawcom.govt.nz>
at 6 January 2006; Police v R (20
February 2004) District Court Dunedin, (Judge O’Driscoll). Hosking v
Runting [2004] NZCA 34 is an analogous New Zealand case, which involved
covertly photographing and publishing the photographs in a magazine of a
celebrity’s
children wearing outer clothing in a public
place.
[27] Standing Committee
of Attorneys-General, above n 11, 19. See further: K Burton, 'Erosion at the
Beach: Privacy Rights Not Just
Sand' (2006) 11 Privacy Law and Policy
Reporter 216; 'Topless Photos Prove Costly', Herald Sun (Sydney), 2
December 2004; 'Parents Warned Over Online Beach Photos', above n
22.
[28] Standing Committee of
Attorneys-General, above n 11, 19. See further: ‘Victorian Charged Over
Indecent Schoolies Photos'
(2006) ABC News Online (Australia), 22
November 2006; 'Schoolies Urged to Look out for Peers', Courier-Mail
(Gold Coast), 20 November 2006; Teacher Refused Bail in 'Upskirt' Case
(2007) News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au>
at 12 May 2007; Jessica
Marszalek, 'Peeping Tom, Thieves Target Schoolies', The Australian (Gold
Coast), 21 November 2006; 'Second Man Held Over Snaps of Women at Tennis',
Sydney Morning Herald (Sydney), 22 January 2007; Tram Voyeur 'Filmed
Up Skirts' (2007) News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au/story>
at 9
June 2007; 'Authorities to Ban Photos 'Up Skirts'', Courier Mail
(Brisbane), 27 May 2007; Crackdown Planned on Pervert Photos (2007)
News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au/story>
at 9 June
2007.
[29] Aubry v Editions
Vice-Versa [1998] SCR 591. JWL, 'HFX OUT HQQ', Halifax
Chronicle-Herald (Amherst), 29 September 2006.
[30] New Zealand Law Commission,
Intimate Covert Filming Study Paper (2004) 2
<http://www.lawcom.govt.nz>
at 6 January 2006.
[31] Department of Justice
Canada, Voyeurism as a Criminal Offence: A Consultation Paper (2002) 1
<http://canada.justice.gc.ca>
at 6 January 2006. This is similar to an
example in Hobart, where a primary school cleaner drilled a hole in the ceiling
of
a toilet and installed a camera to view female students and teachers using
the toilet: Glenn Cordingley, Cleaner Photographs Kids on Toilet (2007)
News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au/story>
at 11 May
2007.
[32] Department of Justice
Canada, above n 31, 6.
[33] Ibid
1.
[34] United Kingdom Home Office,
Setting the Boundaries: Reforming the Law on Sex Offences (2000) 12
<http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk>
at 6 January 2006. Compare Michael A
Scarcella, 'Homeowner's Hidden Camera Helps Send Voyeur to Jail', Sarasota
Herald-Tribune (Manatee County), 14 August 2006; and R Wacks, 'Home Videos:
Is the Surveillance of Domestic Helpers Lawful?' (2000) Privacy Law and
Policy Reporter 49.
[35] New
South Wales, Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 27 February
2004 (Ms Angela
D’Amore).
[36] R v
Davies [2004] QDC 279. This case is similar to an incident reported by the
media, where an ex-policeman filmed two girls showering in his home. The two
girls were aged 9 and 14 years old, and the camera was hidden in a towel:
Ex-policeman Filmed Girls in Shower (2007) News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au>
at 18 May
2007.
[37] Rebecca Cavanagh,
Snapped Naked While Sleeping (2007) News Limited
<http://www.news.com.au/story>
at 9 June
2007.
[38] A Ashworth,
Principles of Criminal Law (Oxford University Press, 5th ed,
2006) 39.
[39] von Hirsch and
Jareborg, above n 13, 19.
[40]
Ibid 20.
[41]
Ibid.
[42]
Ibid.
[43]
Ibid.
[44]
Ibid.
[45] Ibid
19-20.
[46] Ibid
21.
[47] Ibid 4. In these
cases, principles of aggravation and mitigation would be
relevant.
[48] Ibid
10.
[49] Ibid
10-11.
[50] Ibid
11.
[51] Ibid
17.
[52]
Ibid.
[53] Ibid
18.
[54]
Ibid.
[55] Ibid
19.
[56]
Ibid.
[57] Ibid
22.
[58]
Ibid.
[59] Ibid
21.
[60] Ibid
22.
[61] Ibid
21.
[62]
Ibid.
[63] Ibid
18.
[64] Ibid
29.
[65]
Ibid.
[66] Ibid
38.
[67] Ibid
4.
[68]
Ibid.
[69]
Ibid.
[70] Ashworth, above n
38, 37.
[71] See Rothenberg,
above n 18; Calvert and Brown, above n 12; and McClurg, above n 18.
[72] von Hirsch and Jareborg,
above n 13, 24.
[73] Ibid
26.
[74] Ibid
27.
[75]
Ibid.
[76] von Hirsch and
Jareborg, above n 13, 3.
[77] Q
Burrows, 'Scowl because you're on Candid Camera: Privacy and Video Surveillance'
(1997) 31 Valparaiso University Law Review 1079,
1125.
[78] Refer generally to
the offences in Criminal Code (Qld); Summary Offences Act 1988
(NSW); Crimes Act 1961 (NZ); and the Criminal Code
(Can).
[79] See the comment
in the previous footnote.
[80]
See generally the Summary Offences Act 1988 (NSW); and the Crimes Act
1961 (NZ).
[81] Criminal Code (Qld)
s 227A(2); and Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) s 216G(1)(b)(i).
[82] Criminal Code (Qld)
s 227B(1); and Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) s
216J.
[83] Criminal Code
(Qld) s 227A(1)(b)(ii); Summary Offences Act 1988 (NSW) s 21G(1);
Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) s 216G(1)(a)(iii); and Criminal Code (Can) s
162(1)(b).
[84] Criminal Code
(Qld) s 227B(1); Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) s 216J(1); and Criminal Code
(Can) s 162(4). See the Summary Offences Act 1988 (NSW)
generally.
[85] N Lacey, C Wells
and O Quick, Reconstructing Criminal Law Text and Materials, Law in Context
(Sweet & Maxwell, 3rd ed, 2003) 9. Note that this quote was
originally used in the context of the harm principle rather than
in the context
of the living-standard analysis
tool.
[86] Ibid.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2007/26.html