Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
eLaw Journal: Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law |
Author: | Adrian Howe La Trobe University |
Issue: | Volume 2, Number 1 (April 1995) |
"It seems to me that the possibility exists...for a fictional discourse to induce effects of truth...One `fictions' history on the basis of a political reality that makes it true, one `fictions' a politics not yet in existence on the basis of a historical truth."
Foucault [1]
This article offers a poststructuralist reading of the High Court judges' conceptualisations
of property law in Mabo v Queensland
(No 2)[2] in the light of Kevin
Gray's thesis that property is `not theft - it is fraud' and that the
`ultimate fact' about property
is that it `does not really exist: it is mere illusion'. Property is `a vacant
concept - oddly enough rather like thin air'. For
Gray, the interesting
question is how some resources get `propertised' and some do not. As `the
vast majority of the world's human
and economic resources still stand
outside the threshold of property' and thus remain `unregulated by any
proprietary regime', lawyers
interested in the allocation of propertised
resources should be `just as keenly interested when a particular resource
is not propertised'.
In Gray's view, `the refusal to propertise a given
resource is absolutely critical - because logically anterior - to the
formulation
of the current regime of property law'. Yet remarkably, the
fact that decisions have to be made about whether to leave a resource
`outside the regime' remains `unrecognised and unanalysed in legal
discussions of property'[3] To propertise or not to propertise
- that is
the unexamined question which Gray claims lies at the heart of the
`property concept'.
I want to consider how Gray's thesis might apply to Aboriginal land in Australia
- that is, to land occupied by Aboriginal people
in 1788 and still claimed
by them in the late twentieth century. Following Gray's suggestion that a
decision to leave a resource
outside the regime of property law is `a
fundamental precursor to all property discourse',[4] we need to ask: has
Aboriginal land
been propertised in Australia? But this begs another question:
by the rules of which proprietary regime are we to determine whether
Aboriginal land has been propertised? Aboriginal lawyers argue that
Aboriginal groups had their own land law prior to the white invasion.
Thus, Aboriginal land could be said to be already propertised. Certainly,
support for the view that land was regulated by Aboriginal
proprietary
regimes can be found in Blackburn J's famous `factual' finding in Millurpum
v Nabalco, the first Australian land rights
case, that Aboriginal peoples
had `a subtle and elaborate system' - `a system of law' no less - such
that: `If ever a system could
be called "a government of laws, and
not of men"', it was theirs.[5] On the other hand, the reception of
English common
law and, in particular, the doctrine of tenure coduld be said
to have propertised indigenous land under Anglo-Australian law. Alternatively,
statutory land rights schemes could be said to have propertised Aboriginal
land. Indeed, Australia is said to have been `at the forefront
in passing
legislation which has granted ownership of extensive areas of land to
Aboriginal groups'.[6] Furthermore, not only has
the majority in the High
Court in Mabo (No 2) held that there is a concept of `native title' at
common law in Australia; according
to Richard Bartlett, most legislatures
in Australia have moved to give effect to `such rights to land as native
title at common law
recognises'.[7] Thus, Aboriginal land would seem to be
well and truly propertised today, such that the question of whether it
should
be propertised is now redundant.
However, the issues are more complex in that while Aboriginal land could not
be said to stand outside the threshold of property,
it is not fully within
it either. In particular, as we shall see, the High Court judges were
unclear about the proprietary nature
of native title. Moreover, none of
them accorded native title rights the status of rights enjoyed by the owner
of the fee simple
which, according to Gray, `represent the nearest approximation
to absolute ownership known to our modern system of law'.[8] >From
this
we might devise two questions: should common law Aboriginal title be
equated with a fee simple interest and would that have
the effect of fully
propertising Aboriginal land? But rather than pursuing such a positivistic
project, the point of my poststructural
inquiry here - one which is more
faithful to Gray's focal concerns - is to analyse Mabo (No 2) for what it
might tell us about what
constitutes `the "propertiness" of
"property"'[9]. More specifically, I am interested in analysing the different
ways in which the majority judges went about the task of discursively
propertising Aboriginal land by bringing it within the common
law or
rather, by leaving it straddled across the imaginary line dividing propertied
from non-propertied resources.
First, however, I should elaborate briefly on my poststructuralist perspective.[10]
Broadly, poststructuralism (or rather, the kind
of Foucault-influenced
poststructuralist analysis which interests me), examines power relations
operating within regimes of truth.
Within feminist theoretical debates
which question what the foundational category `Woman' authorises and who
it excludes and deauthorises,
Judith Butler has argued that the point of
poststructuralism is `that power pervades the very conceptual apparatus
that seeks to
negotiate its terms'. The aim is `to interrogate what the
theoretical move that establishes foundations authorises, and what
precisely
it excludes or forecloses'. It is most relevant to point out
that Butler highlights the exclusionary processes at work in the operation
of power and that, in particular, she argues that subjects are
`constituted through exclusion, that is, through the creation of a
domain
of deauthorised presubjects, figures of abjection, populations erased from
view'.[11] For that surely was the fate of Aboriginal
land claimants prior
to Mabo (No 2). Interestingly too, Gray declares that a `primordial
principle' of property law is that a resource
can be propertised only if
it is `excludable' - that is, `if it is feasible for a legal person to
exercise regulatory control over
the access of strangers to the various
benefits inherent in the resource'.[12] Prior to Mabo (No 2), Aboriginal
land was, in Gray's
terms, a `non-excludable resource'.[13] Indeed, the
fact that it was not feasible for Aborigines to exclude non- Aboriginal
strangers
from the benefits inherent in their land was a key factor in
Blackburn J's finding in Milurrpum that Aborigines had no proprietary
interest in the land.[14]
If Gray is right that a refusal to propertise a particular resource is `always
an occasion of some moment in the jurisprudence of
property',[15] the
decision of the majority in Mabo (No 2) to overturn a jurisprudence which
had for so long refused to recognise
native title is surely such an occasion
as well. Moreover, to the poststructuralist theorist interested in the way
power pervades
conceptual apparatuses, it is significant that Gray comes
to conceptualise `property' as a `power-relation' - `property is a
power-relation
constituted by legally sanctioned control over access to
the benefits of excludable resources'.[16] More precisely:
"`Property' is the power-relation constituted by the state's endorsement
of private claims to regulate the access of strangers
to the benefit of particular
resources."[17]
After Mabo (No 2) Aboriginal land can be conceptualised as a power- relation
constituted by the state's endorsement of communal native
title claims to
regulate the access of strangers to the benefit of particular resources.
But Gray's point, which is well taken here,
is that whatever legal
fictions are relied on in property cases, they cannot disguise the power
relations at work within legal regimes
of truth.
Of course, much has been made of the role played by legal fictions in Australian
property cases. In particular, the majority's rejection
in Mabo (No 2) of
the legal fiction of terra nullius has attracted much attention, notwithstanding
Richard Bartlett's insistence
that terra nullius is not a concept of the
common law, that it `had never been referred to in any case prior to Mabo
as justifying
a denial of native title' and that `the concept is
essentially irrelevant to native title at common law'.[18] From the
perspective
of an international lawyer however, terra nullius is far from
irrelevant. for example, Gerry Simpson has analysed what he calls the
`interpretive
crisis' brought about when the High Court disposed of terra nullius but
refused to follow international law and the
implications of its own
arguments and find that Australia was conquered territory.[19] What is of
interest here is that the majority's
invention of `a completely new
category of acquisition' - namely, `the occupation of already occupied territory
(or occupation of
land that is not terra nullius') - has had a powerful
discursive effect, notwithstanding the fact that this invention is, in
Simpson's
view, a `semantic impossibility'.[20] But from a poststructuralist
perspective, one sensitive to Foucault's convincing arguments
about the
power of discourse and the lessons of history, much more is at stake here
than semantics.
"...as history constantly teaches us, discourse is not simply that which translates
struggles or systems of domination, but
is the thing for and which there
is struggle, discourse is the power which is to be seized."[21]
Reducing the High Court's new legal fiction to a `semantic impossibility', Simpson
misses the fact that semantics or no semantics,
the new fiction performs a
similar function to that of older legal fictions such as those supporting
the doctrine of tenure. Simply,
property law's legal fictions operate to
conceal power relations at work in the conceptualisation of `property'.
To be clear: it is not that such fictions are false: following Foucault, we
would not read Mabo (No 2) as overturning any falsehoods
or even as dispelling
any myths about land or, more specifically, about the relationship of
Aboriginal people to land and to English
land law. Nor should the Mabo
decision be seen as establishing a historical truth. Rather, its legal
fictions operate to `induce
effects of truth', as Foucault would have it.
Foucault's point is not that truth is `abscent' in fictional discourses,
but rather
that
"One `fictions' history on the basis of a political reality that makes it
true, one `fictions' a politics not yet in existence
on the basis of a historical
truth."[22]
I would argue that this is precisely how one should read the Mabo decision
- as a fictioning of history on the basis of the political
reality of
Aboriginal land claims which make them `true' and as a fictioning of a
politics (a politics of human rights not yet in
existence) on the basis of
a new `historical truth'.
In this connection, we might note Rob McQueen's critique of High Court judges'
understanding of `history'. He suggests that their
historical understanding
is uninformed by an appreciation of `the very different nature of
"historical" and "legal"
truth; and the dangers of
confusing the two'. In particular, they are unaware of the `dangers of
translating a conditional historical
"truth" into an absolute
legal "truth" with a definite performative function'.[23]
Foucault might be less concerned
about distinguishing `historical' from
`legal' truths, but he would agree that the translating of conditional
historical truths into
legal truths has a performative function - it is to
induce effects of truth. Now this, surely, provides a more fruitful and
certainly
a more politicised reading of Mabo (No 2) than one concerned
with `interpretive crises' and `semantic impossibilities', let alone
one
which valorises `scientific history' and science.[24] To read the terra
nullius story as `surreal' and the majority's new fiction
in Mabo (no 2)
as `mysticism', as Simpson does,[25] is to overlook the performative role
played by legal truths. Significantly,
this role is not overlooked by
Toohey J who demonstrates a very good understanding of the function of
legal fictions in his discussion
of the doctrine of tenure in Mabo (no 2).
As Toohey J explains
"the effect of the fiction of past possession by the Crown is to secure
the paramount lordship or radical title of the Crown
which is necessary
for the operation of feudal land law."
Tellingly, he relies on past authority to declare that `since fictions in law
are only acknowledged "for some special purpose",
that should be
taken to be the extent of the fiction'.[26]
Moreover, Toohey J reasons that since fictions work to cancel each other out
- for example, `the fiction of a lost Crown grant answers
the fiction of
original Crown ownership' - it follows that in the present case
"if the fiction that all land was originally owned by the Crown is to be applied,
it may well be that it cannot operate without
also according fictitious
grants to the indigenous occupiers."[27]
We have it, then, from the highest authority that legal doctrines are based
on legal fictions which are designed to perform special
functions. Notably,
in property law they cancel each other out in order to produce new truths
about land grants. Brennan J provides
some pertinent examples. After
noting that the court's rejection of terra nullius removes the `fictional
impediment' to the recognition
of indigenous land rights,[28] he moves on
to tackle the doctrine of tenure - `the fiction that land granted by the
Crown had been
beneficially owned by the Crown'. This fiction, however,
did not give the Crown `an absolute benefical title' to the land: `the
radical
title which is acquired with the acquisition of sovereignty cannot
itself be taken to confer an absolute beneficial title to the
occupied
land'.[29]
By a process of refictioning history, Brennan J is thus able to reject the doctrine
of Crown ownership of land except, as R D Lumb
points out, in the `formal
sense' of the radical title.[30] Brennan J devises a new fiction in which
the antecedent land rights of
the indigenous people `constitute a burden
on the radical title of the Crown'.[31] However, as we have seen, fictions
have a way
of cancelling each other out, and in Mabo (No 2) the court held
that ownership could be vested in the Crown and therefore taken from
indigneous titleholders, the beneficial owners, by virtue of the prerogative
or by legislation. So what one new fictions gives, another
takes away.
Clearly, such fictions are the power to be seized by Aboriginal land
claimants and their opponents. Let us then, proceed
with the task of
reading the Mabo decision as fictional discourse. What do its discursive
moves authorise and what do they exclude
or foreclose?
II
This is a necessarily selective reading, one which confines itself to the received
and invented legal fictions of `property' as they
unravel in Mabo (No 2).
We might note in passing that the majority decision maintains the fiction
of settlement even in the face
of its own historical findings that the
`process of "settlement" involved hostilities against the native
inhabitants'.[32]
The High Court may have rejected the doctrine of terra
nullius, but by clinging to the fiction of `settlement', it resists the
implications
of its own recognition that the acquisition of Australia was
achieved by acts of violence which are strongly suggestive of
conquest.
As for the the fictions of
property, it is appropriate that we return briefly to the doctrine of
tenure and its fiction that all
property originates with the Crown,[33]
for it is this doctrine which is fundamental to English land law and,
consequently, to the
determination of earlier interpretations of the
status of Aboriginal land claims. In Brennan J's view, this doctrine
cannot be overturned
`without fracturing the skeleton which gives our land
law its shape and consistency'.[34] The fiction of royal grants on which
the
doctrine relies - a fiction, tellingly, which was recognised as such
(as a mere `fiction') by Blackstone himself[35] - must remain
because it
induces such crucial effects of truth. However, the doctrine of tenure
needs to be rewritten or perhaps, refictionalised,
to accord with
contemporary `facts' in Australia. Accordingly, Brennan J sets about
fictioning a history on the basis of the political
reality that the
international law theory that inhabited land may be classified as terra
nullius `no longer commands general support'.[36]
Brennan J thus
distinguishes Crown title from Crown ownership of colonial land, declaring
that if the land were `desert and uninhabited,
truly a terra nullius', the
Crown would have an absolute beneficial title to it.[37]
We are returned then, perhaps inexorably, to terra nullius, notwithstanding
the insistence of eminent authority that the determination
of this
question was essentially `irrelevant' to native title at common law. The
majority judges might want their decision to be
hailed as a decisive
rejection of the racist concept of terra nullius, but this claim to fame
is somewhat vitiated by legal arguments
that this concept is irrelevant to
the acceptance of native title.[38] Further, the High Court did not reject
the concept in the
crucial sense of denying Australian sovereignty. Thus
as Bartlett explains, the `real question' in Mabo was whether native title
was part of the common law of a `settled' territory like Australia:
whether or not a region was terra nullius or `settled' `was never
considered to be a bar to native title in Australia or anywhere'.[39]
Noting that the court cited with approval Blackburn J's `factual'
finding
of the original legal system, and implicitly, the original sovereignty of
Aboriginal peoples in Milurrpum v Nabalco,[40]
Bartlett suggests that
`perhaps the true significance' of the rejection of terra nullius was the
recognition of `the falseness' of
the fiction that Aboriginal people were
`without laws, without a sovereign and primitive in their social
organisation'.[41]
With respect, fictions are not false - they induce effects of truth. They are crucial to the telling of what
Rosemary Hunter calls
`competing stories about law and the land'. Hunter
provides an insight into the power of the truth-telling effects of these
narratives
in her evaluation of the white judiciary's terra nullius story
as told in Cooper v Stuart.[42] Citing Lord Watson's declaration in
that
case that New South Wales had been `practically unoccupied, without
settled inhabitants or settled law' when it was `peacefully
annexed to the
British dominions', Hunter comments that for `sheer inventiveness and
historical inaccuracy, this story is more than
a match' for `Captain Cook
stories' about the white invasion as told by Aborigines. These competing
stories function in similar ways
to assimilate `an alien reality into the
speaker's own belief system'.[43] However, `reality' intrudes into this
otherwise excellent
analysis to the point where Hunter comes to interpret
Mabo (No 2) as a repudiation of `the lie of terra nullius'.[44] But
recall,
fictions are not lies - they induce effects of truth. Hunter is
closer to the mark when she reads the rejection of the doctrine of
communal native title in Millurpum as a `rigged contest' in which `the
invaders' story won a convincing victory and the power of
their law to
determine the truth in its own terms was reaffirmed'.[45] For `truth' here
is clearly dependent not on `reality' but
on the power of law - in this
case white Anglo-Australian law and its fiction of terra nullius.
What then, counts now as the truth about Aboriginal land rights? Are they, for
example, proprietary? What is the status of common
law native title in Mabo
(No 2)? While the Court was unclear on
this point, six of the seven judges declared that the content and
nature
of common law native title is determined according to the traditional laws
and customs of the indigenous people who, according
to these laws and
customs have a `connexion with the land'.[46] On the other hand, according
to Brennan J, native title is extinguished
if the indigenous group
"by ceasing to acknowledge those laws, and (so far as practicable) observe those
customs, loses its connexion with the land
or on the death of the last of
the members of the group or clan."[47]
According to Dean and Gaudron JJ
"Even where (from the practical point of view) common law native title approaches
`full ownership'...it is subject to three
important limitations."
First, it cannot be alienated outside `the local native system' except by surrender
to the Crown; second, it is only a personal right
and finally, it is
`susceptible of being extinguished by an unqualified grant by the Crown'
of a fee simple or of a lesser estate
inconsistent with rights under
common law native title.[48] Dean and Gaudron JJ suggest further that it
is preferable
"to recognise the inappropriateness of forcing the native title to conform to
traditional common law concepts and to accept
is as sui generis or unique."[49]
But for those rights to be enforced at common law, the Court found it necessary
to equate them at least to some degree to common
law concepts of property
rights. However, the Court could not reach a consensus on whether these
rights were proprietary or personal.
Brennan J seemed to indicate that
native title rights could fall into either category;[50] Deane and Gaudron
JJ considered the rights
to be `personal only',[51]) while Dawson and
Toohey JJ preferred to avoid any such classification.[52] As Toohey put
it, a determination
as to whether native title is `personal' or `proprietary'
is `fruitless' and `unnecessarily complex'.[53]
Clearly, Deane and Gaudron JJ did not share this opinion. In their view, declaring
native title rights to be personal rather than
proprietary had effects
which could be specified. Native title rights be voluntarily extinguished
by surrender to the Crown. They
could also be abandoned - `lost by the
abandonment of the connexion with the land or by the extinction of the
relevant tribe or group'.(54]
Such devastating effects prompt a question:
was native title classified as personal in order to better render it
extinguishable?[55]
The new truth about native title, that it is
extinguishable by the Crown without compensation, is surely the most
controversial aspect
of the decision. Significantly, three of the judges
allowed for compensation when native title was `wrongfully' extinguished. But
one might ask: how can a wrongful
extinguishment extinguish? It can, if one subscribes to Toohey J's view,
noted above, that legal
fictions perform special functions. In Mabo (No 2),
the fiction of extinguishment functions to cancel out the fiction of
native title.
In the new fictional account, `permissible' wrongful extinguishments
are past events which have generated `reasonable expectations'
on the part
of a considerable number of what might be called `innocent
non-extinguishers'. So
the fiction of `wrongful' extinguishments operates to indicate which past
acts are compensable, while the fiction of `abandonment'
works to exclude
a huge number of possible native title claims.
Puzzling questions remain however. Notwithstanding `the powerful descriptions
of the circumstances in which titles were lost and
stolen', there are few
guidelines in Mabo (No 2) as to what might constitute a `wrongful'
extinguishment.[56] Evidently, the story
of the dispossession of the
Aboriginal people which the majority tells in Mabo (No 2) does not come
within the fiction of a `wrongful'
extinguishment. But what is the
justification for the `radical distinction' between native title and its
extinguishment? Brennan
J distinguishes `skeleton' from `non-skeleton' principles
of the common law, but the crucial question is: `on what ground is
extinguishment
of title skeletal but title not?'[57] And what about the plaintiffs'
argument about their possessory title? As Garth Nettheim notes,
only
Toohey J devoted attention to the argument `from within the common law
based on presumptions of title arising from possession
of the plaintiffs'
predecessors'.[58] Toohey J found much in English property law to support
this argument, concluding that the Meriam
people may have acquired a
possessory title on annexation.[59] Yet he viewed the consequences as
being no more beneficial for the
plaintiffs than native title. Nettheim
disagrees. He claims that a holding that Aboriginal people hold possessory
title in accordance
with Anglo-Australian property law could differ `in
significant ways' from a holding that they hold a native title which is
recognised
but extrinsic to the common law.[60] A full consideration and
recognition of a possessory Aboriginal title however, might disrupt
the
fiction that native title was extinguishable without compensation and
that, more broadly, it conveys rights which amount to something
less than
full ownership. A little more inventiveness, such as that which he
deployed in his discussion of fiduciary duties,[61]
might have allowed
Toohey J to induce a more just effect of truth for Aboriginal people.
III
We return, finally, to the question: should Aboriginal land be propertised or,
rather, fully propertised? For all the
uncertainty
of the content of common law native title, Aboriginal land has
been `propertised' in the crucially important sense that it is property
to
the extent of attracting the protection of s 51 (xxxi) of the
Constitution. It has been suggested that such is the breadth of this
provision that
"..only by the most perverse process of logic could native title escape being
included as a property interest subject to the
constitutional requirement
of just compensation if by a Commonwealth statutory provision it is
acquired by the Commonwealth or another."[62]
Still, while native title is properly classified as a property interest, a question
remains about the equality of property rights
between Aboriginal and
non-Aboriginal title holders. Justice surely demands that the rights flowing
from common law native title
be accorded `the same status as property
rights granted, according to statute, by the Crown'.[63] But as Michael
Mansell argues,
Aboriginal land rights are far from being accorded this
status in Mabo [No 2). The court accepted the view that nomadic people had
rights demanding recognition, but it ruled that `the status of Aboriginal
rights to land at the time of the invasion was not equivalent
to that of
Europeans, but something less'- notably, to that of Indian tribes in North
America. However, this interest in land amounted
only to a right to
occupy. For Mansell, the analogy drawn with other native people and not
with whites indicates the indigenous peoples'
interests in land `are
something less than the interests of Europeans, a racist position indeed'. He points out too, the racism
of the court's
ruling that Aboriginal interests in land are not as `disposable' as those
of whites in that `the group must retain
its identity in a
"biological" manner, the right being a personal one only'. Such
limitations on the transmissibility of
native title as well as its
inalienable nature and the limitations that Aboriginal land rights can be
extinguished and `abandoned'
lead Mansell to conclude that Mabo (no 2)
`merely propounded white domination and superiority over Aborigines by
recognising such
a meagre Aboriginal form if rights over land'.[64]
It is difficult to disagree. The High Court majority in Mabo (No 2) denied
to Aboriginal people the benefit of the common law principle
that possession
gives rise to an interest which is presumed to be a fee simple. Yet as
Gray explains, the fee simple estate occupies
`a pre-eminent position' in
English property law, providing the strongest possible title and carrying
with it `a plenitude of rights
and powers' over land.[65] The principles
of justice propounded by the majority surely require that property
concepts applicable
to all title holders be applied equally. This could be
achieved by assimilating native title to all other titles and held to be a
fee simple. As R B O'Hair argues, while the High court gave Aborigines a
`second rate title', they should not have `worse title'
than non-Aborigines,
they should be compensated for extinguishment and that nothing less than a
`full fee simple' is in order. Like
Mansell, O'Hair suggests that `in
retaining restrictions on alienability and a requirement of continued
adherence to native customs',
the majority ensured that `Australian law
still continues to bifurcate society into black and white'.[66]
Finally, Noel Pearson has criticised the majority for failing to recognise native
title as equivalent to beneficial title. In his
view, native title should
be recognised `as constituting at least the equivalent of the fullest
estate known to the common law, a
fee simple estate'. He notes that only
Toohey J was prepared to support an argument based on possessory title
(common law Aboriginal
title) which would have conferred the fee simple
title.[67] In Mabo (No 2) the Court held that the Meriam people were
`entitled as
against the whole world to possession, occupation, use and
enjoyment'[68] of their tradition lands, but as Pearson argues, the Court's
omission of `ownership' from their characterisation of the Meriam people's
entitlements implies that their title `is not comparable
to the fullest
ownership recognisable by the law'.[69] Yet as Bartlett notes, the Court
declared the need to `fully respect' the
property rights of Aboriginal
people and offered no reason why the content of native title should be
limited. The result was `uncertainty
as to the content of native title'[70]
and, we might add, uncertainty as to the propertiness of Aboriginal land.
So much for `fully
respecting' Aboriginal property rights.
IV
Property, according to Gray, is fraud and illusion. Certainly, the legal fictions
discarded and invented in Mabo (no 2) support the
view that white property
holdings in Australia are fraudulent, established as they are on the
dispossession of the Aboriginal people
Deane and Gaudron JJ conceded as
much when they declared that the association with the dispossession of
Aboriginal people of the
fictions of terra nullius and of the Crown's
unqualified and legal and beneficial ownership of the land disqualified
those fictions
from
"acquiring the legitimacy which their acceptance as a basis of the real property
law of this country for more than a hundred
and fifty years would otherwise
impart."[71]
But the view that property is illusion is not supported by this poststructuralist
reading of the Court's fictional discourse about
Aboriginal land rights.
Rather, this discourse has induced new effects of truth about the
propertiness of Aboriginal land. In Mabo
(No 2) the Court invented new
fictions about the nature of Aboriginal title, not least because they were
worried about describing
that title `as conferring "ownership",
a term which connotes an estate in fee simple or at least an estate of
freehold'.[72]
This could be read as a refusal to properly propertise
Aboriginal land. Nevertheless, as Bartlett has said
"native title, even without the requirement of compensation at common law, is
far from illusory, as the current constitutional
and political furore indicates."[73]
Aboriginal land rights might have been rendered `second rate', but they are
not illusory. The High Court has fictioned a new history
on the basis of
political contingencies and it has fictioned a politics which is coming into
existence on the basis of a new historical
truth - that of the dispossession
of the Aboriginal people.
NOTES
[1] Michel Foucault, `The History of Sexuality' in Colin Gordon (ed), Power/Knowledge
(1980), 193.
[2] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1.
[3] Kevin Gray, `Property in Thin Air' (1991) 50 Cambridge Law Journal 252, 256-7.
[4] Ibid 256.
[5] (1971) 17 FLR 141, 267-8.
[6] H. McRae, G. Nettheim and L. Beacroft, Aboriginal Legal Issues: Commentary
and Materials (1991), 137.
[7] Richard Bartlett, `Mabo: Another Triumph for the Common Law' in Essays
on the Mabo Decision (1993), 64 (my emphasis).
[8] Gray, above n 3, 252.
[9] Ibid 259.
[10] I am using poststructuralism interchangeably with postmodernism. Poststructural/postmodern
perspectives rarely find their way
into property law. Moreover, some
articles claiming such a perspective are not identifiably postmodern. For
example, in one self-proclaimed
postmodern `re-reading' of property law,
the author claims an intellectual debt to Mary Joe Frug who did attempt
to elaborate a
postmodern approach to contract law. However, his
references to `the truth' and to `social reality' belie a postmodern
perspective.
Joseph William Singer, `Re-reading Property' (1992] 26 New
England Law Review 711, 712 and 719.
[11] Judith Butler,`Contingent Foundations and the Question of "Postmodernism"'
in Judith Butler and Joan Scott (eds)
Feminists Theorise the Political
(1990), 7-8 and 13-6 (her emphasis).
[12] Gray above n 3, 268.
[13] Ibid 269.
[14] (1971) 17 FLR 141, 272-3.
[15] Gray above n 3, 268.
[16] Ibid 295.
[17] Ibid 294.
[18] Richard Bartlett, The Mabo Decision (1993), ix.
[19] Gerry Simpson, `Mabo, International Law, Terra Nullius and the Stories
of Settlement: an Unresolved Jurisprudence' [1993] MelbULawRw 7; (1993) 19 MULR 195, 197.
[20] Ibid 198.
[21] Michel Foucault, `The Order of Discourse' in Michael J Shapiro (ed) Language
and Politics (1984), 110.
[22] Foucault, above n 1, 193.
[23] Rob McQueen, `Why High Court Judges Make Poor Historians' (1990) 19 Federal
Law Review 245, 264.
[24] Simpson, above n 19, 197-8 and 210. Simpson borrows the notion of `interpretive
crises' from Thomas Kuhn's study of scientific
revolutions. A critical
comparison of Foucault and Kuhn's work on the relationship between truth,
language, science and power falls
outside the scope of this paper. But
see Michael Shapiro's study which adversely contrasts Kuhn's positivistic
analytical model
with Foucault's more politicised post- empiricist
approach. Michael J Shapiro, Language and Political Understanding: The
Politics
of Discursive Practices (1981), 146-151.
[25] Simpson above n 19, 210.
[26] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 213 (Toohey J).
[27] Ibid.
[28] Ibid 45.
[29] Ibid 47.
[30] R D Lumb, `Native Title to Land in Australia: Recent High Court Decisions'
(1993) 42 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 84, 87.
[31] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 57.
[32] Ibid 77 (Deane and Gaudron JJ).
[33] Ibid 27 (Brennan J, citing Stephen
CJ in Attorney-General (NSW) v Brown).
[34] Ibid 45.
[35] Ibid 47 (Brennan J citing Blackstone's Commentaries).
[36] Ibid 41 (Brennan J).
[37] Ibid 48.
[38] Ibid 138-9 (Dawson J); Sir Harry Gibbs, Foreword to Mabo: A Judicial Revolution
(1993).
[39] Bartlett above n 17, ix.
[40] (1971) 17 FLR 141, 267.
[41] Bartlett, above n 17, x, citing Brennan J in Mabo [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 39.
[43] Rosemary Hunter, `Before Cook and After Cook: Land Rights and Legal Histories
in Australia' (1993) 2 Social and Legal
Studies 487, 490.
[44] Ibid 496.
[45] Ibid 492.
[46] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 3.
[47] Ibid 70 (Brennan J).
[48] Ibid 88-89.
[49] Ibid.
[50] Ibid 51 and 61.
[51] Ibid 110.
[52] Ibid 133 and 195.
[53] Ibid 195.
[54] Ibid 110.
[55] This is the suggestion of Susan Phillips, `Reconstructing the Rules for
the Land Rights Contest' in Essays on the Mabo Decision
(1993) 12.
[56] Ibid 13.
[57] M J Detmold, `Law and Difference: Reflections on Mabo's Case' in Essays
on the Mabo Decision (1993) 42.
[58] Garth Nettheim, `Judicial Revolution or Cautious Correction? Mabo v Queensland'
(1993) 16 UNSW Law Journal 12-13.
[59] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 178 and 211.
[60] Nettheim, above n 58, 12-13.
[61] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 199-205.
[62] Alceo Turello, `Extinguishment of Native Title and the Constitutional Requirement
of Just Terms' (1993) 3 ABL 11. Turello also argues that the majority
decision in Mabo should be read as indicating that extinguishment of
native title amounts
to an acquisition, as required by S 51 (xxxi).
[63] Greg McIntyre, `Aboriginal Title: Equal Rights and Racial Discrimination'
[1993] UNSWLawJl 5; (1993) 16 UNSW Law Journal 57, 58.
[64] Michel Mansell, `The Court Gives an Inch But Takes Another Mile' (1992)
2 ALB 5, 6.
[65]Gray, above n 3, 252-3.
[66] R B O'Hair, `Mabo and Land Rights - Searching for a Golden Thread' in M
A Stephenson and S Ratnapala (eds) Mabo: A Judicial
Revolution (1993) 70-71.
On the other hand, the attempt prior to Mabo to translate Aboriginal
title into English property law by
devising a notion of a communal,
freehold and inalienable title was hailed as `ingenious'. For although
the holder of freehold
can alienate land at will, it was considered by
some to be `contrary to the Aboriginal relationship to their land' if it
were possible
for title-holders to alienate their land and thus dispossess
future generations. Moreover, this view was said to be `strongly supported
by Aboriginal groups, unconvinced by the opposing argument that it is
paternalistic and discriminatory to impose restrictions on
Aboriginal land-owners
which do not apply to non-Aboriginal land-owners'. McRae, Nettheim and
Beacroft above n 5, 179-181.
[67] Noel Pearson, `204 Years of Invisible Title' in Stephenson and Ranapala
above n 66, 79-80 (citing Toohey J in Mabo (1992) 175 CLR 206-7.
[68] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 2.
[69] Ibid 82.
[70] Richard Bartlett (ed), Resource Development and Aboriginal Land Rights
in Australia (1993) 41.
[71] [1992] HCA 23; (1992) 175 CLR 1, 120.
[72] Ibid 75 (Brennan J).
[73] Bartlett, above n 17, xx.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/MurdochUeJlLaw/1995/18.html