![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
![]() |
Experience and Legal Ethics Teaching
JAMES E MOLITERNO*
Teaching about legal ethics1 is just like teaching
about any other area of law. And teaching about legal ethics is different from
teaching about any other area
of law.
Teaching about legal ethics is harder
than teaching about any other area of law. And teaching about legal ethics is
easier than teaching
about any other area of law.
Legal ethics was once
thought to be among the least important things about which American legal
educators teach. Today, legal ethics
is regarded as a quite important thing
about which to teach. Someday soon, I expect, legal ethics will be regarded as
the most important
thing about which American law schools teach.
Where does
this odd mix of observations lead? And what do they have to do with
experience?
WHAT IS TEACHING ABOUT LEGAL ETHICS LIKE?
Legal ethics, or the law governing lawyers, is law. As such, teaching about
legal ethics is in an important way like teaching about
any other area of law.
It was not always seen in this way. Once it was thought that legal ethics was
more etiquette than law, more
manners than enforceable
rules.2 Once legal ethics was taught in the USA by the
preaching method, and students in such courses were known to “chant the
Canons.”3 No longer. Law, at least law as seen as
inclusive of the social policies and moral principles embodied in the positive
rules of law,
is now central to what we teach about in a legal ethics
course.4 None of the leading teaching materials treats
the subject as anything but law. Legal ethics, or the law governing lawyers, is
a body
of enforceable understandings and mandates no different in this respect
from the law of tort or contract. And in some respects, teaching
it is just like
teaching contracts or torts or evidence. Analysis of rules, discussion of cases,
exploration of policy, proposals
for change, and an understanding of
consequences are all as much a part of teaching the law governing lawyers as
they are of teaching
other areas of law. That was far less the case as little as
25 or so years ago when teaching legal ethics was sometimes more preaching
than
policy discussion, more morals than mandates. A close friend of mine tells the
story of the first day of his late 1970s legal
ethics course. The Canons in the
United States had been replaced by the Model Code less than a decade before, and
the professor,
an adjunct, addressed the class something like this: “In
this course we’ll learn some right from wrong and we’ll
learn how to
keep clear of bar discipline. When you look at the Model Code, you’ll see
mostly things called Disciplinary Rules and Ethical
Considerations. To remember what they’re about, remember this:
Follow the EC’s only if you want to be Extra Careful
– Follow the DR’s or there’ll be a Durned
Ruckus.” (Rough translation of Durned Ruckus for the uninitiated
– “lots of trouble.”) Until about that same
time, when Tom
Morgan, Ron Rotunda, and other mid-70s beginning law teachers charted the modern
course, it was largely true to say
that American legal education behaved in a
professionally irresponsible way in the teaching of professional responsibility.
At that
time, materials for teaching the course were few, and aside from
early casebooks such as Costigan’s5 and
Cheatham’s,6 most were recent developments of a
few near-pioneers.7 The new 1970s teaching materials
were mainly problem-based, still reflecting a way of teaching the material that
was different, somewhat
less law-like, than more traditional casebooks. As
materials developed, they became more like materials used in teaching other law
courses,8 and the material taught did the same. The
Canons became the Model Code; the Model Code became the more rule-like Model
Rules; and
eventually the entire range of the course broadened to include an
array of materials beyond the profession’s codes and control
devices
beyond bar discipline.9
At the same time, teaching
about the law governing lawyers is different from teaching about any other area
of law because it is experienced
by the lawyer directly rather than vicariously.
Unlike other areas, in the law governing lawyers, the lawyer is the client. When
a lawyer interacts with the law generally, she does so as a once-removed expert.
The client who comes to the lawyer has the direct
contact with the law; the
client has the tort problem or the contract problem. The lawyer’s
experience with the law is vicarious,
through its application to the client. Not
so the law governing lawyers. Here, the lawyer is the person who experiences the
law and
its application. Here the law is about the lawyer’s relationships
with clients, with other lawyers, with opposing parties,
with courts, with the
public, with the public interest. This simple observation means a great deal to
the pedagogy.10 Since the lawyer’s relationships
and experiences and acts are the subject matter governed by the law governing
lawyers, and
since our students will be those governed lawyers soon, special
advantages may be found in teaching the law governing lawyers through
experiential learning devices such as clinics and simulations. In effect,
lawyers’ activities create the data on which the
law governing lawyers
acts. Students in experiential learning settings create data, too, and their
experiences are the acts to which
the law they are learning about applies.
Learning to be a lawyer is not entirely unlike learning to play a complicated
game. Take
baseball, for example (apologies for choosing my own favourite).
Reading the rules of baseball is a complicated endeavour, running
as they do
several dozens of pages in length. If someone learns those rules, backward and
forward, and could pass a test on their
knowledge of those rules, that person
would still not know how to play baseball. Too many aspects of such an
enterprise can be learned
only by doing, the playing of the game. Judgments
about which base to throw to in which situation, what pitch to throw next, when
to steal a base, when to go half-way and when to tag up on a fly ball, and
countless others can only be understood through repeated
playing of the game; so
too being a lawyer. Learning the rules of ethics is necessary, to be sure. But
learning them without the
accompanying experience is far from learning to be a
lawyer. Experiential learning is uniquely suited to teaching legal ethics. And
that makes teaching legal ethics different from teaching about any other area of
law.
HOW DIFFICULT IS IT TO TEACH ABOUT LEGAL ETHICS?
Many once thought that legal ethics was next to impossible to teach well.
This position was taken, however, at a time when the goals
of the course were
quite different. It was common to hear the question, “If adult students
have not learned right from wrong
by the time we get them, how can we hope to
teach it?” Legal educators do in fact have a substantial impact on their
students’
character development and
“goodness,”11 but making students better
people is no longer a goal of the legal ethics course. To the modest extent that
it may be, it is a goal
equally shared by the entire legal education enterprise
and not held exclusively by the ethics teacher.
In fact, it turns out that
the subject is among the easiest and most enjoyable to teach. With a modest
amount of direction, students
soon see that this course is about them, it is
about their chosen profession, it is the law that governs their own behaviour.
In
no other law subject is the lawyer the centre. Some lawyers may practise
contract law, some tort law, some corporate law. Some lawyers
litigate and have
a special need to know the law of evidence while others are deal makers, never
seeing a courtroom but needing a
special knowledge of securities law or tax law
for example. But every lawyer in every practice setting is the subject of the
legal
ethics course. And every student planning to be a lawyer can see that this
course is about the lawyer’s relationships: with
clients; with other
lawyers; with third parties; with the courts; with the public interest. Engaging
students in the law’s
application to them, its attachment to their
calling, makes the legal ethics course among the easiest in which to generate
interest
and engagement. Of course, legal ethics is hard to teach if you fall
into to trap of moralising or preaching. Of course, legal ethics
is hard to
teach if you fail to take advantage of the special ways of engaging students in
the learning of this most critical material.
Using explicitly experiential
learning devices (such as elaborate simulations, clinics, externships that are
accompanied by seminar
discussion) to teach legal ethics presents special
advantages. The subject is the lawyer and her relationships. Placing students
in
role, allowing them firsthand experience with the experience of lawyering, gives
them special insights into the law governing
lawyers. The data on which this
area of the law is based is generated by what lawyers do. Students, in the
lawyer’s role, sense
the application of the law to their conduct and
simply learn it more effectively. For example, a student may be studying Model
Rule
4.1 and its strictures on dissembling in negotiations. Reading the rule,
reading the cases gets the student to a reasonable level
of understanding. But
place the student in the role of lawyer, have her engage in negotiation on
behalf of a client, and the student
can see and sense the application of the
rule in a new, much more riveting way. The rule, like all the rules of
professional ethics,
is about the lawyer’s own conduct. What better way to
internalise an understanding of such a rule than by experiencing its
application, the tensions it creates, the pulls toward its violation. This is an
advantage in law teaching that applies exclusively
to the law governing lawyers.
We should take advantage of it on behalf of our students.
In a way, even
classroom teaching of the legal ethics course is experiential teaching. Students
who see themselves in role as they
read the cases, work through the
hypotheticals and the problem materials, have a mental experience with the role
of lawyer that is
different from that experienced in other law courses. In
Contracts, the student engages the material with analytical thinking skills,
much as we hope they will learn to engage problems as a lawyer. This learning is
experiential in one dimension. But when the student
sees herself in the
lawyer’s role in studying legal ethics materials, which are about the
relationships of lawyers, the student
experiences a multi-dimensional activity,
with the factual textures of life’s experiences and emotions attaching to
their engagement
with the material.
WHAT MAKES TEACHING ABOUT LEGAL ETHICS IMPORTANT?
Along with professional skills courses, the legal ethics course was long a
second-class subject area in American legal education.
Prior to the 1960s, many
schools offered either no course or a one credit course, and there were few
serious scholars in the subject.
Considered to be both academically light and
practice and profession heavy, the subject was relegated to the edges of legal
education.
Along with the rise of clinical legal education during the 1960s and
70s, largely through the work of the Council on Legal Education
in Professional
Responsibility (“CLEPR”), and spurred by the profession’s
embarrassment in the Watergate scandal
and the subsequent American Bar
Association accreditation response, the professional responsibility course began
its ascent to respectability
and beyond. This connection between clinical
teaching and professional responsibility has existed ever since, but it has
often been
submerged. In recent years, many more efforts to reinforce that
connection have occurred with useful results.12
Recognised or not, this connection helped spur interest in the law of
professional responsibility.
Today the subject is covered at all US law
schools and through multiple courses at many. The subject is taught by a wide
range of
creative teaching methods, supported by numerous, excellent materials.
And a substantial group of first rank scholars devote primary
energy to the
subject. This is as it should be. The subject about which we teach is at the
soul of the profession. It is what lives
with the lawyer daily. It is about the
lawyer’s role, and upon the lawyer’s role is built the legal
profession and ultimately
the justice system. The subject is the profession and
its place in society, its place in the justice system, its place in the
maintenance
of order and social good. What else in the curriculum carries
greater significance?
The subject is about the professional culture. No other
course in the curriculum has the charge to teach what it means to be a lawyer.
We teach about the attributes that distinguish lawyering from other professions
and businesses. We teach about the central principles
that animate our
professional role. We teach the most critical course in the curriculum.
We teach the one course without which the
student cannot venture to begin
the first day of a law career.
AND SO, EXPERIENCE?
American legal education has learned by experience that teaching about the
profession, and a connection to the profession, is critical.
It has learned by
experience that teaching legal ethics is teaching law and that teaching legal
ethics presents unique challenges
and opportunities.
We teachers of legal
ethics have learned from experience that our subject can be taught and taught
well if we take advantage of its
uniqueness, its centre-of-the-legal-profession
status, and its experiential attributes. We have learned that ours is a central
place
in the legal academy, that we represent perhaps the greatest opportunity
for the legal academy to connect with the practising branch
of the profession.
And we have learned that this connection is critical to the future of the
profession.
Our students will learn from experience what it means to be a
lawyer. They can only come to understand what it means to be a lawyer
by
experience. We have a choice: either they can begin learning what it means to be
a lawyer after admission, or they can begin learning
what it means to be a
lawyer while they are with us, at a time when and in a place where that learning
can be guided, can be structured,
can be taught rather than merely learned.
* Professor of Law and Director of the Legal Skills
Programme, College of William & Mary School of Law. For a description of the
ethics and skills teaching programme at William & Mary, see J Moliterno,
Teaching Legal Ethics in a Programme of Comprehensive
Skills Development (1991)
15 J of the Legal Prof 145 or J Moliterno, Legal Education, Experiential
Education, and Professional Responsibility (1996) 38 Wm & Mary L Rev
71, 106-110.
©2001. (2001) 12 Legal Educ Rev 3.
1 It is common to see this subject matter referred to variously as legal ethics, the law governing lawyers, professional ethics, and professional responsibility. I use these terms interchangeably in this essay, the differences among them being irrelevant in this context.
2 J Bond, Present Instruction in Professional Ethics in Law Schools (1915) 4 Am L Sch Rev 40.
3 L Dubin, Professionalism Among Lawyers: The Law School’s Role (1989) 68 Mich B J 850.
4 J Baron & R Greenstein, Constructing the Field of Professional Responsibility (2001) 15 Notre Dame J of Law, Ethics & Pub Pol 37, 39; R Cramton & S Koniak, Rule, Story, and Commitment in the Teaching of Legal Ethics (1996) 38 Wm & Mary L Rev 145.
5 G Costigan Jr, Cases and Other Authorities on Legal Ethics (St Paul: West, 1917).
6 E Cheatham, Cases and Other Materials on the Legal Profession (Chicago: The Foundation Press 1938).
7 T Morgan & R Rotunda, Professional Responsibility Problems and Materials (New York: The Foundation Press, 2000) 7th ed; R Aronson, Problems in Professional Responsibility (St Paul: West, 1978).
8 A few examples among many excellent casebooks: M Schwartz, R Wydick & R Perchbacher, Problems in Legal Ethics (St Paul: West, 2001) (5th ed); S Gillers, Regulation of Lawyers (New York: Aspen,1998) (2nd ed); G Hazard, S Koniak & R Cramton, The Law & Ethics of Lawyering (New York: The Foundation Press, 1999) (3rd ed); N Crystal, Professional Responsibility Problems of the Practice and Profession (New York: Aspen, 2000) (2nd ed); D Rhode & D Luban, Legal Ethics (New York: The Foundation Press, 1995) (2nd ed); T Morgan & R Rotunda, Professional Responsibility Problems and Materials (New York: The Foundation Press, 2000) (7th ed); R Zitrin & C Langford, Legal Ethics and the Practice of Law (Charlottesville, VA: Lexis Law Publishing, 2000) (2nd ed); J Moliterno, Cases and Materials on the Law Governing Lawyers (Cincinnati, O: Anderson Publishing, 2000).
9 D Wilkins, Who Should Regulate Lawyers (1992) 105 Harv L Rev 799.
10 J Moliterno, An Analysis of Ethics Teaching in Law Schools: Replacing Lost Benefits of the Apprentice System in the Academic Atmosphere (1991) 60 Cincinnati L Rev 83, 98-99 (“Apprentice System”).
11 Apprentice System, supra note 10, at 94-97.
12 J Moliterno, Live-Client, In-House Clinics: Some Ethics Issues (1999) 67 Fordham L Rev 2377.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/2001/2.html