Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
LEGAL EDUCATION AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST
ANDREW GOLDSMITH*
[W]hat justifies the existence of a law school [is] the study of the types of legal problems which arise in daily life, and the methods of resolving them satisfactorily, with the least amount of injustice and suffering. Law schools are set up not for the sake of the law or lawyers but ultimately to help human beings to solve legally the problems and predicaments encountered in the pursuit of conflicting social ends.1
INTRODUCTION
Law is both powerful and pervasive. It is also, for
the most part, highly public in nature. The social settings in which legal
considerations
arise are virtually endless. The number of ordinary citizens
affected by legal problems on a daily basis far exceeds the number of
those who
go to court or consult lawyers about such matters, or even those who may seek to
discover their legal position through
a visit to a library, a legal advice
service, or the Internet. In a democratic society, some knowledge of the law is
a highly desirable
commodity. It provides consciousness of entitlements to
benefits and protections and also provides ways of organising and structuring
a
variety of personal and business transactions.
Legal knowledge can therefore
play both a protective and facilitative role. This redistributive potential of
legal knowledge raises
questions about the conceptions, philosophies and
structures of legal education in our society. What should count as legal
knowledge,
and how access to legal knowledge is determined, are profoundly
political questions. As with most political questions, the interests
at stake
are not simply defined by the self-interest of a few individuals or
well-entrenched groups. The range of people affected
by law means that the
stakeholders in legal education in a democratic society cannot be narrowly
limited. While there are some obvious
traditional sectional and private
interests involved, the public interest in legal education is easily
forgotten or ignored. It is precisely this question that concerns me
here.
There is perhaps something almost quaint in the present economic and
political climate about discussions of the public interest. Quaint,
that is,
unless the notion is quickly assimilated under the rhetoric of economic
rationalism and corporate managerialism.2 I want to
suggest that while it is possible to consider this question in terms of the
nature of law students — whether they
more resemble private
consumers or public citizens — there are other pressing
considerations such as who can study law, and the extent to which legal
educators embrace interests other
than simply those of their students and the
legal profession. I shall turn to this question of articulating what the public
interest
in legal education might look like later in the essay.
First
however, I want to makes some observations about the nature of legal knowledge.
Legal knowledge is the currency that links the
legal profession and the law
schools to many aspects of citizenship. I want to look at how this has been
traditionally conceived
by law schools, law students and the profession, and to
suggest some strange shortcomings in this area. These deficiencies raise
questions about the nature and accessibility of legal education in traditional
law schools and more generally within universities
and higher education. In
order to look at these issues, I first examine the idea of a public interest in
legal education and suggest
how the concept might be understood. Then finally, I
make some proposals for how a vision of legal education more reflective of the
nature of legal knowledge and the public interest might be put into practice
— I call this approach an “integrated legal
education
environment”.
LEGAL KNOWLEDGE: TALES FROM TWO CITIES
Legal knowledge is the subject-matter of legal education. It is what gets transmitted to law students by their teachers or that which is the object of student learning within the legal educational setting. What gets taught, and what gets excluded or omitted from the curriculum, are fundamental to the outlook of students and their ultimate professional and academic orientations. On a personal note, I can divide my early understandings of legal knowledge into two phases, from encounters or “visits” to two quite different sites or “cities” of learning. Those “cities” I will call “University” and “Life”. The sharpness of the contrast between the two sources of instruction and the lessons learnt however is not the point. For me, the interesting points to emerge are the needlessness, at least to some extent, of such a striking separation, and its persistence in the face of increasing evidence of its existence and questionable justification. If the consequences of such a cleavage are connected to the perpetuation of narrow professional interests, whether in the law school, among law students, or within the legal profession, then the need to re-examine the relationship between legal knowledge, legal education, and the wider society becomes pressing.
University Tales
As an undergraduate law student, I was exposed to a
traditional legal education for four years. What counted as legal knowledge came
almost exclusively in the form of judicial decisions (case law), supplemented by
some exposure to the contents of statutes. My stay
in “University”
city inculcated a conception of law that was highly formal, document-based, and
the product of a largely
unquestioned and unquestionable set of judicial and
legal institutions. The authority of these institutions was assisted by law
textbooks
that struggled schematically to provide their student readers with a
sense of the coherence and comprehensiveness of law as a body
of knowledge. This
approach was generally aided and abetted by doctrine-oriented exegetical
approaches to classroom teaching and
assessment. For the most part, assessment
took the form of three-and-one-half hour endurance tests in which the capacity
to “discuss
the right cases” in relation to a highly schematic and
uncontroversial set of facts was tested. “Thinking like a lawyer”
was the object of the exercise and indeed the entire law school
experience.
For the most part, the connections between “thinking like a
lawyer” and the rest of human experience were left hanging
or left out
completely. My vague sense of unease at what was happening to me was not enough
to make me challenge what I was being
taught, or to seek refuge in another
faculty. Instead I meekly and silently tried to make sense of the messy morass
of case law that
seemed to be our constant fodder. Much of the time, this seemed
like drudgery, and when the spirits got low, even punishment. The
student
culture played its part in ensuring widespread acceptance of the
system.3 Leaving aside the issue of the subjects
required for admission to practice, there was also remarkable student conformity
in relation
to which other subjects to take. In the corridors, rather than in
the classrooms, students, not law teachers, advised other students
which
electives were advisable for practice or otherwise worth taking. Yet the curious
thing was how we seemed to accept things.
For myself, and I suspect for the
overwhelming majority of my class, the drawbacks of legal education were offset
by the (then) quiet
promise of something sweet at the end of the road. Legal
education’s focus upon legal doctrine in “University”
city was
dry, and indeed remote, but it smelt of power and held the prospect of
employment in a potentially highly lucrative profession.
Life Tales: Playing “The Game”
The revelation that in order to practise law,
“something else” was required in the way of legal knowledge was
however
not long in coming. My first vivid introduction to “Life”
came in the form of the search for employment as an articled
law clerk. Having
managed to obtain an interview with a well-known Adelaide establishment law
firm, I found myself being questioned
by a senior partner about issues almost
exclusively unrelated to the content or experience of my stay in
“University”.
Whereas in approaching the interview, I had felt
reasonably competent on questions of law, I quickly found myself floundering for
the “right kind” of legal knowledge, or at least, professional
preparation. Was my father the well-known member of the
stock exchange? He was,
and still is, not. Did I play First 18 football at school? I played hockey. What
about First 11 cricket?
I played tennis. Did I belong to the school rowing team?
My high school did not offer rowing. By this stage, I realised things were
not
going well.
I was therefore hardly surprised by the fact that an offer of
articles was not forthcoming. It provided however my first sharp introduction
to
(what was for me) a new field of legal knowledge, the sociology of the legal
profession. Being a lawyer, I learnt abruptly but
very effectively, had only
something to do with having a degree in law, and access at least to the more
exalted levels of the profession
was determined by factors largely unconnected
to what went on in the law lecture theatre or library. I had learnt the law, but
I
hadn’t (until now) known about “the rules of the
game”.
Not deterred however, I persisted in my ambition to practise
law, and soon after completion of articles, found myself in a two-solicitor
office in a country town. I was about to have my second sharp lesson in
“Life” on the nature of legal knowledge. My youthful
idealism for
the practice of criminal law, and particularly the representation of legal aid
clients, came to the fore. I was apparently
unusual by local practice standards
in the number of trials, rather than pleas of guilty, I would handle in the
magistrates’
court. While I relished the trial experience, trials clearly
meant more work for the local prosecutor and for the visiting magistrates.
There
was certainly a touch of Perry Mason about my early approaches to criminal law
practice, but like Perry, I saw my actions as
justified by the values of what
American lawyers call due process. After a few months, I was taken aside by a
solicitor from another
firm in the district for a “friendly word. He had
been drinking at the local hotel with the local prosecutor, as it seems was
their Friday habit. The prosecutor had been complaining to him that I was taking
on “hopeless” or “pointless”
cases, and insisting on
taking them to trial. It would be far more convenient, and a better use of
everybody’s time, my colleague-in-law
advised me, if I were more
“reasonable” about my criminal clients, and persuaded more of them
to plead guilty. Then,
he reassured me, the prosecutor would be more likely to
look upon me with favour.
From this experience I learnt another valuable
lesson in legal knowledge — in order to practise criminal law in the
courts,
you needed to accommodate yourself to the informal demands of the other
participants. Your client was very low down the list of claimants.
It was not
simply a matter of following formal procedures and defending rights. The
“unwritten” rules of the situation
demanded my
compliance.4 Life Games: Proceed Directly, Don’t
Digress
The peculiarities of the legal field, and what counts as legal
knowledge, were revealed further in a third experience in my first
lecturing job
at the University of Warwick. By this stage I had completed postgraduate work in
criminology as well as law, and the
head of Warwick law school encouraged me in
teaching criminal law to use as much criminological material as I wished.
Warwick then
(and I think still) prided itself on its “law in
context” philosophy.5 This distinguished it very
markedly from traditional English law schools, which had not acknowledged for
the most part the existence
of legally relevant knowledge outside of law
reports, statute books, and legal textbooks. What was to shock me however were
the reactions
of Warwick students towards these two types of knowledge. In
lectures, so long as I referred to cases or statutory provisions, the
students
were models of absorption and transcription. Heads would be down, hands would be
scribbling furiously, the class was acting
with singularity of focus. But once I
dared to stray beyond the smooth, almost frictionless terrain of case law and
statute books
into the more diverse but comparatively rough territory of
criminology, there was a sea-change amongst the students.
My classroom forays
into interdisciplinarity were rewarded by pens dropping, restless shifting of
body positions, and low murmurings
and other signs of distraction. While
initially disconcerting for me as a first-time classroom teacher, I soon
discovered that this
pattern of behaviour could be quickly brought to an end by
the simplest of techniques — the mention of the “next”
or
“latest” case. This was indeed a sobering experience. Students
possessed strong, highly conventional conceptions of
“relevant”
legal knowledge which in turn imposed enormous pressure upon their
teachers.6 Those of us law teachers who aspired in some
sense through our professional roles to act as social reformers or critics of
even the
most gentle and constructive kind needed to be modest about our
capacity to shape and mould the next generation of would-be lawyers.
Notwithstanding the rhetorical claims made in some law school promotional
literature, the agendas for legal education, including
what counted as legal
knowledge, were strongly determined according to a variety of consumer and
professional criteria, and not simply
according to academic
ones.7
From these vignettes and from my subsequent
experiences, I draw the lesson that the relationship between traditional legal
education
and legal knowledge has been, and continues to be in many quarters,
strangely perverse. While lawyers in practice operate largely
according to a
body of shared, informal legal knowledge, there has been little or no pressure
from either the student consumers or
the prospective employers of law graduates,
in particular the profession, to acknowledge the value of it in law
school.8 The closest to this has been the movement for
greater “skills training” and measures of competence in legal
education.
9 This is not at all the same kind of legal
knowledge I have been describing here; in any event, the “skills
movement”
in Australia probably owes more to academics and students than
to demands from the practising profession.10
This
perversity clearly owes a lot to student conservatism. Their expectations of
legal education, it may be suggested, derive as
much if not more from television
and the media, their families, and the profession as they do from their
teachers.11 In many law schools, there is evidence of
there being “two cultures”, a “student culture” and an
“academic”
one.12 Their separateness is
marked as much as anything by the disparity between the research and writing
interests of academic staff and
the content and focus of undergraduate
courses.13 The conventional preference of students for
a relatively arcane and limited form of legal knowledge does not sit empirically
or responsibly
with law’s social location or significance.
The problem
in part is that, as students, they do not yet know what it is to practise law,
so that they are not well-situated to make
judgments of this kind. However they
are aided and abetted by the legal profession and, for the most part, law
teachers, who are
at least constructively complicitous in this strange
disjunction. Here the impact of the professional core of the LLB (what has come
to be known as the “Priestley 11”14) upon
curriculum development has been enormous, but the extent of its influence upon a
more generalist notion of legal education
has arguably been greater than has
been necessary.15 It still seems, for example, that
there is a resistance or reluctance among many legal academics towards teaching
critically or contextually
in these core areas, using materials from other
disciplines and perspectives.16 While some reluctance
may arise where academics feel inadequately trained in these other areas,
student resistance and its influence
upon such choices cannot easily be
discounted. In any event the “core’s” palpable influence upon
the entire LLB
curriculum is indisputable, and lends legitimacy, and some
persuasive force, to the pattern of teaching confined to legal exposition
leavened perhaps by a little policy. The relative prestige of this
profession-endorsed vision of legal education sits strangely alongside
the
realities of professional legal practice. The narrowness and high abstraction of
this vision also makes it difficult to translate
for a wider audience.
The
possibilities for challenging and transforming long-established conceptions of
legal education are obviously not assisted by the
current institutional
configurations and range of interests represented in mainstream legal
education.
The traditional law school, with its focus upon teaching students
to “think like lawyers”, continues largely unmoved by
critical legal
studies, deconstructionism, law and society, and even law and
economics.17 Feminist theory has been a partial
exception to this general resistance.18 Nothing much is
likely to alter without changes in attitudes towards legal education outside as
well as inside the academy, including
on the issue of accessibility of legal
education. A broader range of students and subjects, partly through an expanded
range of law-related
programs, is needed if the hegemony of the
practice-oriented LLB is to be challenged. “Law”, as it has been
conceived
over the last fifty years, I hope to show, does not adequately address
the public interest in legal education. A more expansively defined field
of legal knowledge generally, and range of educational opportunities within the
law school, would be an appropriate corrective to the dominant narrow
professionalism of the current legal education arrangements.
THE PUBLIC INTEREST IN LEGAL EDUCATION
So far I have made two basic points. The first has been that what has tended to count in law schools as legally relevant knowledge is often far removed from what it is important to know and understand about how the law works outside law schools, whether it be in lawyers’ offices, magistrates’ and other courts, government departments, private businesses, or the home. Secondly, there is the fact that traditionally, law students, law schools, and the profession have effectively worked together to perpetuate this vision of legal knowledge.19 This de facto collaboration in protecting a highly abstract and remote view of law has undoubtedly contributed to the elevation and mystification of law, adding to, or at least buttressing, its professional standing.20 For these and other reasons, it is, I suggest, perfectly proper to inquire whether the interests currently being served by legal education are the appropriate ones, or at least the only ones that should be taken into consideration. After all, what is in issue is the form of professional education for membership of one of the most powerful professions in our society, and one still substantially funded from the public purse.21
What is “the public interest”?
To pose a question about legal education and the public interest is to suggest at least a couple of things; first, the need to justify the present form of legal education against a standard of evaluation external to those interests immediately affected by or implicated in legal education, and secondly, the connection between the often immensely personal if not private nature of legal problems, and the broader social interests in justice, equity, and peaceful co-existence. As well as having to be considered in respect to the market and the state, I wish to suggest that the nature and role of legal education needs also to be discussed and justified in the public sphere.22 The state and civil society, the market as well as personal relations, each has a stake in the preservation, dissemination and extension of legal knowledge.23
The State’s Public Interest
The legal profession has a long history of having to
justify its privileged position both to the state and to the
market.24 The state’s interest in competition
policy and regulatory issues has meant that often these two spheres overlap. A
spate of
recent Federal and State inquiries into the legal profession points to
the strong government interest in the competitiveness and
accountability of the
legal profession.25 These are arguably examples of
public interest examinations of the legal profession. Another example, but one
with a broader “social
justice” orientation was the Commonwealth
Access to Justice Advisory Committee’s report, Access to Justice: An
Action Plan.26
In relation to legal
education, the need for careful justification stems from the power exercised by
the profession in society and
the fact of public expenditure on all forms of
university education, including legal education. A very recent example of a
public
interest inquiry of the first kind is the Australian Law Reform
Commission’s Issues Paper, Review of the Adversarial System of
Litigation: Rethinking Legal Education and
Training.27 The periodic discipline reviews
initiated by the Commonwealth government, the last done of law in 1987 by the
Pearce Committee, provide
other examples.28 The need
for ongoing or regular public interest examinations of both the legal profession
and legal education has been accentuated
by the decline in legal aid
availability, the worsening access to lawyers’ services in the light of
this funding downturn29 and the dramatic increase over
the past decade in the number of law students and law schools in
Australia.30 Whether the governmental approaches to
date to the public interest aspect in legal professional issues, including
education, have
taken a sufficiently broad approach should be open to question,
and is a matter worthy of debate given the resource implications
of funding law
places in universities.
A Public Interest Conception of Legal Education?
The idea of a public sphere however points to a
non-state, or non-governmental, view of the public interest in legal
education.31 This would conceivably link closely to
questions of citizenship, equality of opportunity and justice in liberal
democratic societies.32 Access to higher education in
law would presumably arise under this notion. The justness, rather than simply
the coherence or principles
of operation, of the existing legal arrangements
would arguably help define another approach to this question. While the criteria
for evaluating the public interest issue will ultimately be determined
politically through discussion and argument, different experiences
and empirical
evidence can play a role. The “assessment of the consequences of policies
for the members of the public”33 ought to be a
central aspect of any such inquiry.
Implicit then in such a public interest
notion of legal education should be some conception of
other-regardingness, a positive attempt to take into account
others’ perspectives on legal education, including a commitment to
sensitively and
effectively inquiring into the full range of views and interests
at stake. In the pursuit of the distinctive and the different, such
an approach
needs also to take account of the common elements of our predicament as citizens
and fellow inhabitants of social space,
and hence of shared interests and
interdependency. Such an approach:
reject[s] the increasingly prevalent notion that human behaviour is based on self-interest, narrowly conceived. [It] argue[s] for a more complex view of both individual behaviour and social organization — a view that takes into account duty, love, and malevolence. Focusing on the “pro-social” motivations, [it] acknowledge[s] individuals’ commitments to moral principles, concern for others, “we-feeling”, and readiness to cooperate when cooperation does not serve self-interest narrowly conceived. [It] recognize[s] the extent to which existing institutions depend on public standards and a public spirit.34
If the notion of public interest in legal education
still appears a little fuzzy, we should not worry too much. To some extent, as
Bayley has noted, the lack of clarity surrounding its meaning misses the point
of raising the public interest question: “its
genius lies not in its
clarity but in its perverse and persistent moral intrusion upon the internal and
external discourse of rulers
and ruled alike”.35
There is no shortage to the ways in which scholars and thinkers have sought to
convey the “public interest”.36
There
is not the space or need here to canvass them all. The language itself (as well
as the meaning) used to convey a wider set of
concerns than just self-interest
varies to some extent. In the field of law, law professor Anthony
Kronman’s articulation of
his “lawyer-statesman” ideal in his
book The Lost Lawyer refers to the “simple but potent idea that lawyers
have
an obligation to serve the public
good.”37 Here, Kronman refers to a
duty upon lawyers:
.consciously to promote not only their clients’ private interests but also the integrity of the rules and institutions that form the framework within which these interests exist. On their view, for a lawyer to lead a responsible professional life, he must keep one eye on the legal arrangements that define the broad background of his everyday work. He must take an active interest in the betterment of these arrangements and be prepared to contribute to their improvement and repair. Failing this, the practice of law loses its status as a calling and degenerates into a tool with no more inherent moral dignity than a hammer or a gun.38
Kronman’s legal professional ideal suggests
the importance of a commitment to the values of the legal system as well as to
those
of the client. By implication, Kronman is suggesting that legal education
should pay closer attention to these concerns.39 He
also refers to the importance of being able to exercise the combination of
sympathy and detachment in dealing with others.40 This
requires what he calls deliberative imagination, “the capacity to
entertain a point of view defined by interests, attitudes,
and values different
from one’s own without actually endorsing
it”.41 In a similar vein, Martha Nussbaum has
recently used the phrase “poetic justice” to refer to a judicial
sensibility towards
decision- making developed through an exposure to
literature. In this scheme, the roles of “fancy” and
“sympathy”
are deemed crucial to “fully rational”
judging, through which the judges “educate not only their technical
capacities
but also their capacity for
humanity”.42
In ideas such as these, one can
start to see a sense of the public interest that is open to different interests,
viewpoints and, indeed,
feelings. The calls to “imagination” and
“fancy” point to the capacity to identify with others in very
different
personal circumstances and social situations as well as to a capacity
to conceive of how things might be different from the present.
While neither
Kronman nor Nussbaum are suggesting an unbridled expression of different
emotions and attitudes as part of the legal
process, both are pointing to
greater openness, awareness and sensitivity by lawyers and judges towards those
with whom they come
into contact. Ultimately however, from the diversity of
considerations, the person judging must reach a decision-point that is
integrative
as well as balanced. In the path followed in reaching that decision,
the procedural implications suggested by Nussbaum and
others43 point to a more comprehensive sense of public
interest than one narrowly drawn in terms of two parties to a particular
dispute. A
fuller conception of legal knowledge, it can be argued, would provide
a stronger information base, as well as a more sufficient set
of principles, for
acting in this capacity.
So what does the discussion so far signify for a
public interest concept of legal education? From Kronman and Nussbaum, we derive
a focus upon the legal system as a whole, and an openness to different
interests and needs. There is also the idea of an expansion of inputs or
markets. The “public interest” method involves questioning the
motives and interests currently represented in legal education,
and identifying
other actual or potential stakeholders. What, for example, are the consequences
of present limits upon access to
legal education? How adequate are our
performance indicators for measuring legal professional commitment to public
service? What
other interests are being ignored or denied in the present
arrangements? Any privileged professional position should be expected
to
withstand public scrutiny and questioning of this kind. Through such questions,
we begin to focus upon “the legal system”
more broadly, rather than
just “the legal profession”, “current law students”, and
“clients”.
Rather than seeing just “clients”, we ought
to think about “potential clients”, and “people with legal
problems”. Similarly, it makes sense to include not just current law
students, but those now or in the future likely to be
“interested in legal
knowledge”.
The “community of
concern”44 for legal education, I am therefore
arguing, can be, and ought to be, defined quite broadly. It is important to
realise that this
definition need not be driven by particular values or
ideologies. If one accepts that a part of a public interest examination involves
an assessment of the consequences of legal educational policy, we are
forced to consider the impact of policy in concrete terms. Any evaluation
however would require some ideal standard. We might
well think about a
comparison between the outcomes of present policy and institutional arrangements
(in terms of the present stakeholders),
and other conceivable policy outcomes
(arising from an examination of a wider or different range of stakeholders and
interests, or
from an interpretation of relevant values, for example access to
justice). We might consider outcomes or consequences in terms of:
graduate
satisfaction with the course taken, the workplace destination of graduates after
different specified periods (for example
2 years, 5 years, 10 years), the
involvement of graduates in pro bono legal work and other forms of legal
assistance, the participation
by graduates in other spheres of community
service, the participation of non-law students in law courses, and the
socio-economic,
racial and gender characteristics of those admitted to law
school and of those who graduate. Other measures might conceivably be
devised to
assist in this kind of assessment exercise. Clarifying the consequences of legal
education in these and other ways is
crucial to the evaluation process inherent
in a public interest focus.
One measure worth developing is the degree of
outreach to other educational programs and community needs. How accessible
are law courses, and indeed legal academics, to the wider community? Such an
inquiry could look at the involvement
of law teachers in teaching programs
outside the professional law degree, but might also explore the range of actual
or possible
educational courses that would benefit from the inclusion of some
legal knowledge. The market should not be presumed only to speak
with its
present voice; other, new markets for legal education ought also to be explored.
The contours of legal education’s
“community of concern”
should not be taken to be immutable or optimal in their present form.
EXPANDING THE CONCEPTION AND AVAILABILITY OF LEGAL EDUCATION
In an age of heightened reflection upon the goals and purposes of law school,45 William Twining46 has been a principal contributor to these debates. In a recent essay, Twining reports upon the state of legal education in a mythical country called Xanadu. There, he finds some assumptions and features that will not strike the Australian reader as entirely unfamiliar. There are the following widespread assumptions about legal education in Xanadu:
I propose concentrating on assumptions 2, 3 and 5. These reflect directly upon questions of access to legal education by different groups within the community, the domination of law schools by the professional legal education model, and inevitably, the scope of legal knowledge within the university.
A Core Professional Commitment?
In Australia, there can be little doubt that the core
mission of law schools remains to provide primary legal education for those
seeking to qualify for the right to practise in the private legal profession.
Only really in New South Wales now is there a system
for qualifying for practice
without the completion of a university law degree.48
While it is customary for law deans and law school handbooks to allude to the
high number of law graduates who will not practise
law, and then to extol the
value of the LLB in providing a general liberal education, the prospect of a
right to private practice
continues to dominate law student culture. The
strength of this feature, despite the potentially dampening effect of current
economic
conditions and the huge growth in supply of law graduates over the past
five years, is perhaps testimony to the even worse job prospects
faced by
graduates in other disciplines.49
What was once a
guaranteed meal ticket now perhaps more accurately resembles a right to apply
for legal jobs. Student concerns about
their future employment prospects are
perfectly understandable and reasonable. They are too quickly ignored by some
traditionalists,
who would see the concept of a valid academic university course
limited to the study of history, literature, philosophy or the
classics.50 Ironically, it may be suggested, these
academics ignore some of the lessons of their own disciplines: that values and
priorities
can change, and that material conditions remain enormously
influential in shaping current values and priorities. Inevitably however,
as I
have suggested earlier, these real world lessons place pressures upon what
counts as legal education, and apparently inevitably
constrain any reformist and
public interest inclinations of students and their teachers
alike.51
Schlegel has commented on this tough
student streak:
Students are intensely practical creatures. If they need a credential, they will sit through unbelievable dreck [sic] to get it. But once the study of law is cut off from the reasonably automatic professional credential, they will want to know that they are learning something “practical”, something that they can use for some purpose in the world. Justifications for the use or non-use of state power by one or another of the cast of characters that comes with the State these days is on the whole not a very useful thing.52
Law students are not alone in being practical creatures in this sense. “Knowing-why”, the traditional aspect of the university approach to knowledge, must now contend far more often with “knowing-how” in a wide range of disciplines for the attention of the modem mass university’s increasingly vocation-oriented students.
Something More from Legal Education?
Whether the high levels of demand for law will
continue for much longer cannot be known nor taken for granted at this point.
What
does seem certain however is the continuation of university law schools as
primary providers of professional education leading students
to qualify for
private practice. If anything, it seems likely to grow further, through
university involvement in Professional Legal
Training and skills
courses.53 The question really is what else should
legal education offer? To what extent will the private practitioner image
continue to squeeze
out other approaches to legal education, and will the
professional snob syndrome persist in university legal education? Even if their
grip on legal education is loosened, the claims of “relevance”, if
not actual “vocationalism”, seem likely
to remain.
In company
with Twining, I would argue strongly that legal education has the potential to
offer much more, and to more people, than
it does at present. However, ways
around the current mental and material constraints need to be found. Why, as
Twining asks, do we
insist on defining legal education, and who constitutes a
law student, by reference to the LLB program? The limitations upon access
to
university places in law, even with the recent expansion in the number of law
schools, remain considerable compared to the demand.
More law schools or more
law places could easily be filled if recent patterns of demand are any
indication, and if demand were the
sole consideration. However historically, the
influence of socio-economic factors upon who gets admitted to law has remained
pronounced,
and with the increasing move towards student-funded university
places, is likely to get worse.54 The recent move to
differential Higher Education Contribution fees, putting law in the highest
bracket, of course does nothing to
de-emphasise the exclusivity and privilege
associated with being a LLB student, nor indeed the virtue of legal careers
other than
highly remunerative ones. It is unfortunate however that what is
effectively a progressive tax on the projected future earnings of
lawyers acts
also to reinforce the distinctiveness of the LLB student, and to quarantine the
study of law further from those already
unable to afford or otherwise obtain
access to an undergraduate law degree. It is equally regrettable that this move
is likely only
to further strengthen the strong claims of corporate and
commercial law practice over the vocational imagination and commitments
of law
students.55
TACKLING THE PROFESSIONAL SNOB SYNDROME
Affordability is merely one aspect of access to legal education. Another way of improving access would be for the barriers currently restricting movement of students between the study of law and other disciplines to be relaxed, so that students from other fields are able to take courses in law-related topics. Why should students in other programs be prevented from taking topics offered as part of the LLB? Obviously, in some cases, the knowledge base acquired by students in earlier years will limit the degree and form of integration possible, but differences of academic background should not justify a lack of imagination about how this might be done. Separate small groups and different assessment methods are two possible responses, though I would argue that quarantining of this kind should only be justified where absolutely necessary.
Benefits of Student Diversity
Given the historical bias in law student selection
processes, steps in this direction would facilitate greater exchange between
students
of different types, some of whom will possess motives for studying law
other than to qualify for practice in the private profession.
Greater student
diversity becomes an obvious consequence. In a sense then under this scheme,
legal education ceases to be the prerogative
of a relative few, but can be part
of the education of a much wider and diverse group of students. The interaction
between more diverse
types of students is likely to affect not just the students
but their teachers. Students will be exposed to a wider variety of contexts
for
the study of law, while law teachers will have to respond to this diversity in
their approach to teaching.
While offering for some teachers the opportunity
to bring their scholarly interests (for example gender and racial inequality
issues)
into stronger and more authentic alignment with the content of the law
school curriculum and the biographies of their
students,56 this is at least a challenging, if not
actually threatening, scenario for many law teachers and mainstream law
students. Law’s
customary foundation in tradition and authority has had
until now a settling if not exactly anaesthetising effect upon the materials
and
methods of legal education. To alter admission policies or access to law topics
in the direction indicated, and to become innovative
and interdisciplinary in
one’s approach to law teaching, is to invite all involved to “see
the settled from the angle
of the
unsettled”.57
The questioning of fundamentals
clearly poses a threat to much conventional professional legal education, as
customary legal knowledge
and values are juxtaposed with the materials for
effective social criticism. 58 But this should not
threaten good professional legal education. In the words of former
University of Chicago law professor, Edward Levi, “the professional school
which sets its course by the
current practice of the profession is, in an
important sense, a failure.”59
The question
for any school involved in professional education located within a university
becomes just how robust can critical self-examination become in a particular
professional school? It can be ventured here that in the United States at
least, the truly great law schools have been inclined to follow, rather than
ignore, Levi’s advice.60 The question that has
not yet been clearly answered in Australia is whether law schools have
sufficient real autonomy from the profession,
the state, or the market to be
able to undertake this kind of fundamental criticism.61
Such self-examination, it should be pointed out, is just as vital to a vibrant
and healthy profession as it is to the values of the
university or indeed to
what might be considered the public interest.
Another way of tackling the
professional snob syndrome is to proliferate the range of courses and programs
taught within legal education
institutions. To some extent, this will have been
begun through the integration of non-LLB or non practice oriented students into
“mainstream” law-related topics. But those students will by
definition be pursuing other programs. While these programs
might conceivably
stretch across the range of disciplines taught in the university (the
“service teaching” model), there
is obviously plenty of scope for
students who wish to pursue either academic or vocationally oriented programs
with a substantial
legal focus to be accommodated within “legal
studies” or paralegal type programs.
This already exists in a variety
of institutions including Southern Cross University (which offers both paralegal
and legal studies
programs in addition to the LLB), and La Trobe University,
where legal studies and law are taught in the same school (the School
of Law and
Legal Studies). Flinders offers a similar (though more restricted) range of
choices, through a combination of programs
provided by the School of Law and by
Legal Studies within the Department (formerly School) of Cultural
Studies.
The stigma attached by some students to such courses by comparison
with the LLB (ie “real”) law topics might indeed be
reduced by
shared teaching arrangements. There is of course the strong possibility that
students enrolled in non-LLB courses will
seek admission subsequently to the
LLB. Of course this already occurs in institutions offering different types of
law program. Given
current student consumerism, this is hardly surprising.
Moreover, it is difficult on academic grounds to find fault with such a
progression
if the nature of legal education has indeed become more outward-
focused and public-spirited. Indeed, the shifts in conception of
legal education
argued for here would make it a perfectly reasonable, even natural, step for
students in the kind of integrated legal
education environment I wish now to
propose.
AN INTEGRATED LEGAL EDUCATION ENVIRONMENT
The case for drawing together a variety of different teaching and research functions, united by a commitment to providing wide access to legal knowledge (along the lines I have conceived of it), is one largely made already by Twining. As a consequence, I shall use his work to some extent, but try to go further to sketch out how these functions might be integrated in ways that are largely self-supporting and enable diversity of approach and enhancement of access to law-related teaching and research. My emphasis here is on the reasons for an integration of legal education functions and some possible ways of doing so, rather than an insistence upon a particular administrative structure for doing so; as always, the case for function ought to precede the case for form or structure.62
The ILC Model
In Blackstone’s Tower, Twining introduces us to what he calls the academic model of a university law school, represented in a very ambitious form by a model known as the International Legal Center (ILC) model. It is ambitious precisely because it seeks to meet a range of professional as well as academic objectives, whilst remaining independent of the legal profession:
Law schools, perceived as multi-purpose centres, can develop human resources and idealism needed to strengthen legal systems; they can develop research and intellectual direction; they can address problems in fields ranging from land reform to criminal justice; they can foster the development of indigenous languages as vehicles for the administration of law; they can assist institutions involved in training paraprofessionals; they can help to provide materials and encouragement for civic education about law in schools and more intelligent treatment of law in the media; they can organise, or help organise, advanced specialist legal education for professionals who must acquire particular kinds of skill and expertise.63
The discussion of a model developed over twenty years ago, apparently for implementation in a Third World context,64 should not seem misplaced or irrelevant in the present Australian setting. The range of interests in legal education here is equally broad as those contemplated by the ILC model, and the problems in Australia today of resourcing education and training programs to meet these interests are perhaps more analogous to the situation of Third World countries than when the model was first devised in the mid-1970s.
Teaching Across Programs
A blending of functions within a particular
university environment would offer a number of benefits, some of which have
already been
spelt out. Perhaps most significantly however, the exercise of
integrating different types of research and teaching, on academic
as well as
economic grounds, would help remove what Twining has called the professional
snobbery syndrome. Consider some ways in
which this might work in practice. Law
teachers might well teach their preferred topic areas but in a variety of
academic programs.
It would be conceivable, for example, for an academic
interested in criminal justice to teach criminal law in the LLB program, to
offer a course on criminal law and procedure for paralegals working in the legal
aid field, and as well, though not necessarily all
at the same time, either a
postgraduate diploma subject for law and other graduates specialising in
criminal law and justice issues,
or a criminal procedure course as part of
Professional Legal Training offered by the university.
Another academic, say
without formal legal qualifications but with interests in women’s issues,
might teach a course on family
violence and child protection for social workers
and students majoring in legal studies, contribute to the teaching of family or
criminal law in the professional law degree, and play a part in an
interdisciplinary MA program on gender. In the commercial field,
an academic
might offer courses in dispute resolution to law, legal studies, and commerce
students doing degrees, while putting on
continuing education courses for
working professionals and short courses for interested members of the
public.
There are clear practical as well as academic advantages arising from
this kind of integration. It avoids the artificial divisions
that exist around
areas of legal knowledge dictated by professional status and program, rather
than knowledge or skill affinities.
In the era of the modem mass university,
boundaries of this kind are increasingly hard to sustain. If they can be
removed, it allows
the possibilities of considerable economies of scale, as
specialist knowledge in particular areas is presented to different audiences
in
a variety of educational awards. As already indicated, some of this integration
can occur where appropriate through joint teaching
of students from different
programs in the same topics. More imagination and less rigidity on this front
will have institutional
benefits in terms of efficiency and access, while
academically, it will simultaneously allow greater specialisation of teaching
staff
and more diversity of programs. This last point is significant for both
the undergraduate and postgraduate markets. Greater diversity
at the
postgraduate level will enrich the teaching opportunities of staff who presently
have few if any opportunities at this level.
Enriched Research Possibilities
The research function remains a significant and
integral component of this ILC model. By admitting a more diverse student body
to
an enhanced range of legal education programs, there is the promise of
identifying a wide range of social problems in need of legal
research and
problem-solving. Until the strong grip of commercial law practice on legal
education and the imagination of many law
students is loosened, the value of
research looking at social issues will remain diminished and largely irrelevant.
The kind of specialisation
mentioned in relation to teaching would contribute to
the possibility of research of the “social problem” kind, as a
broader range of perspectives from the student body as well as research methods
are brought to bear upon key issues. Academics would
be encouraged to engage in
more active, empirical forms of research, and not simply remain tied to their
library desks and offices
in the production of legal knowledge. Research then
would move away somewhat from the predominant form of legal scholarship (the
justification of legal doctrine) towards more empirically and experientially
informed forms of scholarship. The humility and healthy
scepticism towards
vested interests and opinions engendered through work of this kind might serve
to lend some realism to some of
the more library-driven proposals of traditional
legal research and teaching, and to encourage more self-criticism among those
pursuing
legal careers.
Yet another way of undertaking non-doctrinal legal
research would be through interdisciplinary research teams, linking lawyers with
academics from other disciplines in the sciences, social sciences and
humanities. Academics without formal training in law need not
be artificially
introduced into the research environment in order to undertake this research, as
the greater range of legal education
courses offered, and the relative
independence from the legal profession offered by a broader variety of programs,
would mean that
staff with qualifications in other disciplines than law would
form part of the teaching of law-related topics and courses. It is
already the
case that the most academic and, for that matter, prestigious law schools in the
United States, have people from other
disciplines (philosophy, history,
economics, sociology etc) either on full-time staff or as cross-appointments.
The appointment of
Martha Nussbaum, a philosopher, to teach legal ethics in the
University of Chicago law school, of David Luban, another philosopher,
to work
in the law clinic as well as teach ethics at Georgetown Law Center, and of
sociologist Jerome Skolnick, to teach criminal
justice at Berkeley, points to
the kinds of interdisciplinary possibilities to be found within a university
environment committed
in imaginative ways to legal education. In this respect,
as Twining points out, while clearly not all law schools are born equal,
there
is something indeed puzzling about the commitment by law schools to pursue
near-identical missions and be judged by the same
standards. The same argument
could be made here in our own backyards.
In an integrated legal environment,
there is even more reason and opportunity for acting imaginatively and doing
things differently
in the field of legal education. Only if we have the courage
to do so will legal education cease to be simply training future professionals
to “think like lawyers”, and expand to become “thinking about
law” by a much wider group. Then perhaps, we
will have moved closer toward
legal education in the public interest.
CONCLUSION
Discussion around the notion of a public interest
in legal education is useful in order to call into question the seemingly
natural dominance of the traditional law school model over the fields of legal
knowledge and legal education. Without attempting to be definitive about what
this notion implies, I have suggested a focus upon
recognition of different
interests in legal knowledge and ways of incorporating a greater diversity of
stakeholders in legal education.
By making legal education more accessible and
by expanding the realm of legal knowledge, by taking it out of the law library
and
into the average streets, ordinary homes and businesses of everyday life,
the students of law, legal studies and other programs can
be exposed to a much
more diverse and rich range of materials and opportunities for learning than is
currently offered by law schools
in most universities.
An integrated legal
education environment means closer links with the community, as well as between
staff and students in cognate
academic programs. The consequences for those
involved ought to be useful as well as intrinsically valuable. Opportunities of
this
kind will provide students with valuable practical aptitudes and
orientations relevant to opportunities in the job market as well
as with a
deeper appreciation of the contribution of law and legal knowledge to questions
about justice and fairness. The results
for staff come in the form of enriched
research and teaching opportunities. For the community, the benefits take the
form of greater
access to legal knowledge and programs, and the reassurance that
legal knowledge more adequately embraces a range of their interests
and their
collective well-being. An integrated legal education environment, by reason of
its championing of this conception of legal
knowledge, its commitment to groups
other than the legal profession, and its provision of greater student access and
diversity of
academic programs, is well-positioned to avoid narrowly conceived
academic and professional self-interest. It is one means by which
legal
education can aspire to serving the public interest.
* Foundation Professor of Legal Studies, Flinders University,
Adelaide.
This paper was first given as the author’s inaugural address
to Flinders University, November 1997. It draws upon work funded
by a Large ARC
Grant, awarded to the author in 1993 to look at the relationship between legal
knowledge and legal practice. The assistance
of the ARC is gratefully
acknowledged. The author also would like to thank the referees for their
constructive comments on the paper,
as well as Kathy Mack for her useful remarks
on an earlier draft.
©1999. (1998) 9 Legal Educ Rev
143.
1 S Hook, Commentary, in D Haber, & J Cohen eds, The Law School of Tomorrow: The Projection of an ldeal (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1968) 41.
2 See M Pusey, Economic Rationalism in Canberra: A Nation-Building State Changes Its Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1991).
3 See for example R Granfield, Making Elite Lawyers (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard UP, 1992); A Goldsmith, Warning: Law School Can Endanger Your Health [1995] MonashULawRw 11; (1995) 21 Monash U LR 272 on law student socialization and law student culture.
4 Years later, I wished I had read some of the relevant literature on this phenomenon while I was a law student. The most obvious piece would have been A Blumberg’s The Practice of Law as a Confidence Game (1967) 1 L & Soc’y Rev 15.
5 There is a literature on the establishment of Warwick law school and its achievements. See for example Sherr, & Webb, infra note 7; also W Twining, Law in Context: Enlarging a Discipline (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1997).
6 In the current era of compulsory (compulsive?) student evaluations of subjects, one cannot help wondering about the extent of the pressures to take the “line of least resistance” to student pressure of this kind.
7 For an evaluation of the Warwick law school approach, see A Sherr, & J Webb, Law Students, the External Market, and Socialization: Do We Make Them Turn to the City? (1989) 16 J L & Soc 225.
8 I have suggested that there are clear instrumental arguments for teaching knowledge of this kind in law schools. See A Goldsmith, An Unruly Conjunction? Social Thought and Legal Action in Clinical Legal Education (1993) 43 J Legal Educ 415.
9 I have commented on this trend in another piece, Heroes or Technicians?: The Moral Capacities of Tomorrow’s Lawyers (1996) 14 J Prof Legal Educ 1.
10 The practising profession’s complicity in retaining a “black letter law” approach to legal education can be observed in other areas. For example, the lack of importance attached to clinical legal experience by many large law firms recruiting law graduates by implication underlines the relative value of classroom based subjects for students aspiring to practise in large firms. In the United States however, the American Bar Association’s Legal Education and Professional Development: An Educational Continuum (the MacCrate Report) (Chicago: ABA, 1992) suggests a stronger professional interest in these aspects of legal education.
11 See Granfield, supra note 3; Goldsmith, supra note 3.
12 On different kinds of student culture see BR Clark, The Higher Education System: Academic Organization in Cross-National Perspective (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983).
13 See W Twining, Blackstone’s Tower: The English Law School (London: Stevens/Sweet and Maxwell, 1994); Twining, supra note 5; J Schlegel, Talkin’ Dirty: Twining’s Tower and Kalman’s Strange Career (1996) 21 L & Soc Inquiry 981, at 999.
14 So named after the Chairman of the Consultative Committee of State and Territorial Law Admitting Authorities, the Hon Mr Justice LJ Priestley of the Court of Appeal, Supreme Court of New South Wales. The reports of that committee have been published in Centre for Legal Education, Uniform Admission in Australia (Sydney: CLE, nd).
15 See C Sampford, Rethinking the Core Curriculum in J Goldring, C Sampford, & R Simmonds, New Foundations in Legal Education (Sydney: Cavendish, 1998).
16 Student expectations play their part. However, from conversations I have had with a number of law colleagues, the reticence towards adopting more diverse approaches to the teaching of core legal subjects is surprisingly strong. Apart from the power of student expectations, I am at a loss to adequately explain or understand this.
17 Law and economics has had a considerable impact upon law school curricula and teaching in the US and Canada, along with feminism. In Australia, it would seem, feminism has been a stronger influence than law and economics. The panic that really quite modest inroads by these “subversive disciplines” have caused in the United States was evident, for example, in the concern expressed by Judge Harry Edwards in The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession (1992) 91 Mich L Rev 34.
18 The growing number of women law students and teachers seems likely to be related to this receptivity towards feminist theory in law schools.
19 See Granfield, supra note 3; also D Kennedy, Reproduction for Legal Hierarchy in D Kairys ed, The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982).
20 A Abbott, The System of Professions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988).
21 Of course, as the level of student contribution to the cost of legal education rises, there is the real chance that the possibility of such an inquiry, and indeed the pertinence of one, will become more difficult to argue persuasively. In a market driven higher education sector, by definition, the public interest will be defined in terms of the ability to exercise individual consumer or exchange preferences.
22 This notion is often associated with the work of Jurgen Habermas. It suggests a place for unconstrained discussion, debate and action, distinct from the interests of the state or the logic of the economy, on matters of broad public concern. See D Villa, Postmodernism and the Public Sphere (1992) 86 Am Pol Sci Rev 712.
23 It should be noted that I am not using the term “public interest” in a strictly legal sense. In the latter sense, it often arises in defamation actions. There, a matter of public interest has been taken to refer to one “such as to affect people at large, so that they may be legitimately interested in, or concerned at, what is going on, or what may happen to others: London Artists Ltd v Littler [l968] 1 WLR 607.” See Butterworths Concise Australian Legal Dictionary (Sydney: Butterworths, 1997) 324.
24 R Abel, Between Market and State: The Legal Profession in Turmoil (1989) 52 Mod L Rev 285.
25 See for example Australia, Trade Practices Commission, Study of the Professions – Legal – Final Report (Canberra: TPC, 1994); Access to Justice Advisory Committee, Access to Justice: An Action Plan (Canberra: Access to Justice Advisory Committee, 1994); Victoria, Reforming the Legal Profession: Report of the Attorney General’s Working Party on the Legal Profession (Melbourne: Department of Justice, 1995).
26 Access to Justice Advisory Committee, supra note 25.
27 ALRC, Review of the Adversarial System of Litigation: Rethinking Legal Education and Training (Sydney: ALRC, 1997).
28 Commonwealth Tertiary Education Commission, Australian Law Schools: A Discipline Assessment (the Pearce Report) (Canberra: AGPS, 1987).
29 See for instance F Regan, Rolls Royce or Rundown 1970s Kingswood? Australia’s Legal Aid in Comparative Perspective (1997) 22 Alt LJ 225; Senate Legal and Constitutional Legislative Committee, Inquiry into the Australian Legal Aid System: Report 3 (Canberra: Parliament of Australia, 1998) ch 3.
30 In 1996, there were 27 law schools and nearly 21,000 undergraduate law students in Australia (in 1987, there were only 13 law schools): Centre for Legal Education, The Australasian Legal Education Yearbook 1996 (Sydney: CLE, 1996) 25.
31 It would clearly be a conceptual mistake to confuse the political interests of the government of the day with the public interest of the nation or society as a whole.
32 Graziano has written that “the public interest has been one of the major normative underpinnings of liberal-democratic thought.” L Graziano, On Special Interests, Public Interests, and Unequal Representation (1996) 17 Int’l Pol Sci Rev 307, at 307.
33 R Flathman, The Public Interest: An Essay Concerning the Normative Discourse of Politics (New York: Wiley, 1966) 8, quoted in V Held, The Public Interest and Individual Interests (New York: Basic Books, 1970) 224.
34 J Mansbridge ed, Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990) ix.
35 Cited in D Martinson, Ethical Public Relations Practitioners Must Not Ignore “Public Interest” (1995) 10 J Mass Media Ethics 210, at 211.
36 See Held, supra note 33; also W Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989) 76-90 and J Chan, Raz on Liberal Rights and Common Goods (1995) 15 Ox J Legal Stud 15 (dealing with the “common good”).
37 Kronman, The Lost Lawyer: Failing Ideals of the Legal Profession (Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1993) 364. Emphasis added.
38 Id.
39 In fact, Kronman devotes a large chapter of his book to the role of law schools. See id at ch 4.
40 Id at ch 2.
41 Id at 326.
42 M Nussbaum, Poetic Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life (Boston: Beacon Press, 1995) 121.
43 Another writer in this tradition is Martha Minow. See particularly her Making All the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion, and American Law (Ithaca NY: Cornell UP, 1990).
44 I am indebted to the work of Marion Smiley for this notion. See Smiley, Moral Responsibility and the Boundaries of Community: Power and Accountability from a Pragmatic Point of View (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992) 195ff.
45 See for example P Birks ed, What are Law Schools For? (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1996); F Cownie ed, Law School: Global Issues, Local Challenges (Dartmouth Publishing, forthcoming).
46 Twining, supra note 13.
47 W Twining, Rethinking Law Schools (1996) 21 L & Soc Inquiry 1007, at 1014.
48 This is known as the Legal Practitioners’ Admission Board (LPAB).
49 For a discussion of relative graduate salaries and employment opportunities see V Morgan & B Guthrie, Graduate Starting Salaries 1997: A Study of the Earnings of New Graduates in their First Full-time Employment in Australia (Melbourne: Graduate Careers Council of Australia, 1998).
50 Every law academic, I venture to suggest, will have had the experience of meeting someone, usually another academic, who actively questions the academic value of university legal education in comparison to the humanities or some other field of university teaching and research.
51 See Granfield, supra note 3; also R Stover, Making It and Breaking It: The Fate of Public Interest Commitment during Law School (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1989).
52 JH Schlegel, Talkin’ Dirty: Twining’s Tower and Kalman’s Strange Career (1996) 21 L & Soc Inquiry 981, at 999.
53 Flinders and Adelaide law schools have both begun to be involved in PLT teaching in 1999, following the demise of the University of South Australia scheme.
54 See for example J Goldring and S Vignaendra, A Social Profile of New Law Students in the Australian Capital Territory, New South Wales and Victoria (Sydney: Centre for Legal Education, 1997); also see B Birrell & I Dobson, Equity and University Attendance: The Monash Experience (1997) 5 People and Place 49.
55 See Granfield, supra note 3.
56 So long as law students continue to be so unrepresentative of the general population, the perception of “lack of relevance” in many areas of contemporary legal scholarship (for example, critical race theory, feminism, critical legal studies) will continue to dog the efforts of their teachers to introduce materials of this kind into the classroom.
57 R Unger, Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1987) 65.
58 In the words of Alan Wolfe “[t]hose who defend tradition, believe in authority and obedience, and assign a relatively low priority to reason and argumentation are not going to find social criticism to their liking”: Wolfe, Marginalized in the Middle (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996) 34.
59 E Levi, Point of View: Talks in Education (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969) 105.
60 One of the characteristics of “top” American law schools has been their commitment to pluralism and diversity of scholarly interests and perspectives in their appointments processes. One only has to look at the academic staff of law schools such as Stanford, Berkeley, Harvard, Yale, New York University, and Georgetown to realise this.
61 The experience at Macquarie law school in the 1980s (with the threats to close the law school, and concerns about the employability of Macquarie graduates), the University of New South Wales some years earlier, over professional recognition of their “Lawyers and Society” course, and the kerfuffle at Melbourne law school a couple of years ago over the importance attached in the LLB curriculum to feminist legal theory, indicate the strong professional interest in law schools not straying too far from convention.
62 Here I share Professor Faith Trent’s view that “[t]he challenge in a changing university ... is to build a way of operating which focuses on function rather than structure, which enables the university to respond and which increases cooperation and respect rather than maintenance of difference and territory. Our internal arrangements need to make us able to respond to challenges, rather than placing obstacles in the way of the development of intellectual pursuits”: Trent, The University: A View from the Underside, Inaugural Professorial Lecture, Flinders University, November 1991, 7.
63 Twining, Blackstone’s Tower, supra note 13, at 54.
64 Twining, id, does not make the provenance of the report, which I’ve been unable to locate, entirely clear. However, the examples given in the quotation above, and Twining’s longstanding interest in legal education in many different countries, including those of Africa, lead me to this conclusion.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/1998/7.html