![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
![]() |
FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGIES AND A LAW-IN-CONTEXT
JURISPRUDENCE COURSE: A NEW ZEALAND EXPERIENCE
NAN SEUFFERT*
I wish to focus on developments in feminist epistemology, or theories of knowledge and knowledge creation, and how they relate to teaching. I will first discuss the feminist epistemologies that have influenced my teaching. Then I will focus on how feminist epistemology influenced the design, the substance and the methods of teaching a law-in-context Jurisprudence course at the University of Waikato. As the title suggests, mine is a New Zealand experience, and the perspective of an American who has been in New Zealand for four years. This essay is an attempt to think through some of my experiences in New Zealand in light of my North American theoretical background. I hope that presenting my experiences will stimulate thinking from Australian perspectives.
FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGY
Feminist theories of epistemology start with the
recognition that women can be knowers and that the experiences of women can
produce
knowledge.1 Focus on the experiences of women
in feminist epistemologies has resulted from critique of traditional notions of
aperspectival objectivity.
These critiques have deconstructed claims that
knowledge is objective, revealing that such claims tend to cloak male experience
based
knowledge.2 Feminists’ recognition that
legal knowledge has been created from the perspectives of men, especially a
relatively small group
of men in positions of power, has revealed that
traditional assumptions of aperspectival objectivity in law have masked what is
actually
its “relentless perspectivity”.3
Recognising the male perspective of the law results in challenges to claims of
objectivity, and claims that universal applicability
of laws results in
fairness. Examples of this perspectivity include its failure until quite
recently to recognise sexual harassment
as an injury, and construction of the
laws concerning rape from the perspective of the (male) rapist.
Feminist
challenges to the relentless perspectivity of the law have initiated a fairly
intense theoretical debate, ranging from efforts to re-create
“grand theory”4 to
“postmodern”5 critiques. Postmodern
critiques of foundational theory include critiques of the foundational
assumption that there is an essential
“women’s
experience”. 6 At the same time, women of colour
have challenged feminist theories that exclude their
experiences.7
These debates have raised a series of
difficult epistemological questions. Can any knowledge or theory claim
objectivity or universality?
What claims can we make for the knowledge that we
produce? How widely relevant is knowledge? Is the only possibility for theory,
as Lucie White claims, a “situated, reflective history of ... practice..
.”?8 Do these critiques suggest that the only
theories that we can produce are reflections on our own experiences that might
help others
to think more deeply about their experiences? These are the
questions that I have taken with me into teaching.
Two theorists have
provided insight into these questions and have influenced my teaching. Katherine
Bartlett has argued for an epistemological
stance of “positionality”
that “acknowledges the existence of empirical truths, values and
knowledge, and also
their contingency.”9 Common
aspects of experiences may provide useful categories and a basis for knowledge
that is identifiable as true. The recognition
of these “truths” must
be coupled with the realisation that the knowledge is limited by context. The
individual perspectives
of knowledge producers reflect the contested historical
and political sites in which they work.10 Context also
refers to the social positions of the producers of knowledge, including
positions of relative power or powerlessness
along axes of class, race, gender,
sexual orientation, culture, religion, able-bodiness and other socially
constructed groups. Geographical
location is another component of knowledge.
Positionality recognises that the way in which each person is situated, or
positioned
in society, affects what she perceives as truth and
knowledge.11 Truth and knowledge are therefore also
positioned, or situated.
Donna Haraway, in turn, has made an important
contribution to the development of feminist epistemologies by arguing that we
should
value knowledge claims that are situated, rather than looking for what
has traditionally been called objectivity.12
Traditionally “objectivity” has referred to those knowledge claims
that we are prepared to recognise and value. Claims
of objectivity in knowledge
production have been false claims that the knowledge producer can see the
subject of the knowledge from
all perspectives equally at once without actually
being situated anywhere, “the god-trick of
objectivity.”13 Haraway argues that, “Only
partial perspective promises objective vision.”14
Objectivity in her view involves taking responsibility for the partiality of
knowledge production.15 In turn, knowledge producers
are accountable for the knowledge produced.16 We cannot
claim that we are not responsible for the “truth” that we
“reveal.”
Recognition that all knowledge is situated does not
mean that all claims to knowledge have equal value. Relativism is the mirror
image
of objectivity,17 but it makes the same claims:
it is also “a way of being nowhere while claiming to be everywhere
equally.”18 Both objectivity and relativism deny
the significance of location and the stakes in where one is positioned that are
reflected in
the knowledge that one produces.19
How
then do we decide which knowledge claims we should value? There are at least two
places to start. First, we might value knowledge
claims that are situated,
rather than looking for claims of the traditional objectivity. We might value
knowledge that encompasses
an inherent recognition of its situated aspects and
its partiality, thus leaving space for other knowledge claims from other
perspectives.20 Knowledge producers who recognise the
importance of their own perspectives in producing knowledge, who make attempts
to broaden their
perspectives, and who acknowledge the inevitable partiality of
the knowledge produced, are taking steps towards producing valuable
knowledge.
The discussion of situated knowledges suggests, for example, that producers
of knowledge who are in privileged positions produce more
valuable knowledge
when they recognise the limitations of their perspectives, and therefore the
limitations of the knowledge that
they produce, especially with respect to
groups whose oppression they do not share.
Haraway provides clues to a
second approach to valuing knowledge that builds on “feminist standpoint
epistemology” while
addressing its critiques. Recognition of a
“standpoint” from which one creates knowledge is recognition of the
location
or situation for the knowledge production.21
Feminist standpoint epistemology usually claims that the material life activity
and victimisation of the oppressed, (usually focusing
on women), gives women
access to knowledge that the oppressors (men) cannot share. For the oppressed,
knowledge production requires
engagement in struggles against oppressors:
[O]ne must engage in the intellectual and political struggle necessary to see natural and social life from the point of view of that disdained activity which produces women’s experiences instead of from the partial and perverse perspective available from the “ruling gender” experience of men.22
Standpoint
theorists claim that feminist standpoint epistemology produces a
“truer” knowledge than that produced from
the “partial and
perverse” experience of men.23 Implicit is the
claim that it results in an objective science: that women’s experiences of
struggles against male domination
provide objective access to the relations of
male domination and female suppression.24 In making
these claims, it is usually assumed that women share an authentic nature and
therefore a common standpoint, or point of
view, and common experiences upon
which a feminist jurisprudence, for example, could be
based.25 Such assumptions essentialise woman’s
identity.
The essentialist assumptions underlying feminist standpoint
epistemology, and its claim of a feminist standpoint, must be subject
to careful
scrutiny.26 Such claims, especially when made by
privileged white women, are subject to the same critique levelled at the
“perverse perspective”
of the “ruling gender.” The
resulting “universal scientific truth” may exclude the experiences
of many women.
Indeed, the underlying assumption of a “true” or
“authentic” nature or identity of all women in the work
of feminists
who use standpoint epistemology in law has been specifically critiqued from a
methodological perspective.27 Such essentialist
positions obscure crucial differences among women.
However, these critiques
do not require standpoint epistemology to be discarded. There is good reason to
believe that vision is better
from below the powerful; people who fit into
socially constructed groups that are oppressed have more complete knowledge
about the
oppression and about those in positions of power with respect to their
oppression than do those with power.28 The survival of
people in oppressed groups has often depended on their knowledge of the
oppressors-it is in the interests of the
oppressed groups, and not of the
oppressors, to know about the oppression.29 Haraway
adds to feminist standpoint epistemology the recognition of the situated aspect
of the knowledge produced by the oppressed
groups. Women as an essentialist
group do not produce objective or “scientific” knowledge. All
knowledge is situated.
Feminist standpoint epistemology suggests that
middle-class white women who engage in political struggle may have better
knowledge
about their own sex and gender oppression by middle-class white men
than may middle-class white men. This does not make the knowledge
produced
objective. It is a value judgement that the situation, or perspective from which
the women produce the knowledge provides
them with a more complete
understanding, or is a better perspective than that of the men.
Valuable
knowledge might be produced by oppressed groups about their own oppression with
respect to groups that impose and enforce,
or even simply benefit from, the
oppression. Such knowledge might be seen to be most valuable when it also
recognises its limitations:
the extent to which it is based upon common
experiences and who is included in the groups that share the experiences, and
thus how
widely applicable the knowledge is.
USING FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGY TO TEACH JURISPRUDENCE
The important characteristics of positionality and
situated knowledges for my purposes, include first, recognition of the
partiality
of knowledge and limitations in producing knowledge, and second, the
recognition that the position and contexts in which knowledge
is produced form
an integral part of the knowledge. I would like to talk about how these
characteristics influenced the design, substance
and teaching methods of a
law-in-context Jurisprudence course. As context is important, let me sketch in
the particular context in
which the University of Waikato Law School and the
Jurisprudence course developed.
In New Zealand, the legitimacy of the
British form of government, at least with respect to Maori, the indigenous
people of NZ, is
based on the 1840 Treaty of Waitangi. The British generally
claim that in the Treaty of Waitangi Maori people ceded sovereignty,
or the
right to govern the country, to the British. In the Treaty, it is clear that
Maori are guaranteed certain things, including
te tino Rangatiratanga, which can
only be loosely translated as chieftainship, and control over taonga (treasures)
and resources,
such as fishing.30 I think it is fair to
say that people have different views on what the Treaty of Waitangi
means.31 Since at least the late 1960s many Maori
people have asserted that they did not cede sovereignty. The most logical and
well-developed
interpretations of the Treaty of Waitangi suggest that what Maori
people were agreeing to, and what the British knew that Maori people
were
agreeing to, was the British coming into the country to govern the British,
while the guarantee of te tino Rangatiratanga ensured
that Maori people retained
the right to govern Maori people.32
In the
mid-1980s the Department of Justice commissioned Moana Jackson, a Maori lawyer,
to conduct a study of Maori people and the
criminal justice
system.33 Jackson talked to 2000 Maori people at hui
(or meetings) using culturally appropriate methods of communication (and
conducting a
far more comprehensive study than the one commissioned). Jackson
wrote an eloquent indictment of the racism of the New Zealand Criminal
Justice
System. He critiqued its basis in a monocultural philosophy and critiqued the
substantive outcome of criminal convictions.
He concluded, based on the argument
that the Treaty guaranteed te tino Rangatiratanga, that parallel legal systems
for Maori and
non-Maori were mandated by the Treaty.34
Debate continues around Jackson’s proposal for parallel legal systems.
It is in this political and historical context that the University of
Waikato School of Law was established. The goals of the school
were to develop a
bicultural approach to legal education, to teach law in context and to provide a
professional legal education.35
Curriculum Design
The development of a course in Jurisprudence provided
an opportunity for implementing the goals of the school while recognising the
first important characteristic of feminist epistemologies, the partiality of all
knowledge production. Jurisprudence is required
in the LLB programme in Law II
and was taught prior to the core curriculum (Property, Torts, Crimes, Corporate
Entities, Contracts
and Dispute Resolution). Initially, there was a team of
three faculty members developing the Jurisprudence course, none of whom was
Maori. It was initially decided to teach the course through concepts such as
sovereignty and rights, which provides a fairly traditional
approach to the
course. Based on the interpretations of the Treaty with which I was familiar and
the stated goal of developing a
bicultural approach to teaching law, I suggested
that both Maori and British legal concepts should be included in the course.
In the second year of the course we began to attempt to develop the
bicultural aspects, and these developments involved recognising
the partiality
of our own perspectives in producing and reproducing knowledge in our teaching.
In New Zealand a substantial body
of literature exists in which Maori people
critique non-Maori for researching and writing about Maori culture and thereby
simultaneously
appropriating and redefining it.36 As
one of my colleagues, Annie Mikaere, has written, “Maori concepts have
been bandied about [by Pakeha commentators] almost
as if they were qualified to
understand them.”37 Jackson adds that such people
tend to be “neo-colonialists who neither understand nor respect Maori nor
or culture.”38 These critiques raised questions,
about who should be deciding which Maori concepts to teach in the Jurisprudence
course and who
should be teaching the concepts, simultaneously.
Taking these
critiques seriously in answering these questions involved recognising the
partiality of our perspectives and therefore
our limitations in producing and
re-producing Maori legal concepts. However, this acknowledgment was not the end
of the road. If
we were not qualified to teach these concepts then who was? And
who should decide who was? And who should decide what these people
would teach?
Or when or how they would teach it and how it would interact with the rest of
the course? Limited time and resources
influenced how quickly we could address
these questions. Our first tasks included consultation with our Maori colleagues
(recognising,
of course, that they had plenty of their own work to do) and
asking them to recommend people who could provide guest lectures on
these
topics. We also later realised that the Maori component of the course was
fragmented because the Maori concepts were taught
scattered throughout the
course; this was probably a reflection of the fact that the course was still
structured around the British
concepts.
One result of our recognition of our
limitations that I did not foresee was that once the course was structured to
include Maori concepts,
and we made the effort to ensure that those concepts
were taught by Maori experts, Annie Mikaere, whom I have quoted, became
interested
in teaching the course. One of the reasons that she became
interested, she said, was because the course was now structured in a manner
that
clarified the need for participation by a permanent member of staff who was
qualified to teach the Maori legal concepts. In
the fourth year the course was
restructured and she taught Maori Jurisprudence in a block at the beginning of
the year.
Substance and Context
The second important characteristic of feminist
epistemologies, the recognition that the position and contexts in which
knowledge
is produced form an integral part of the knowledge, influenced how I
taught even the traditional theorists included in the course,
such as Austin. To
illustrate my teaching of law in context, I will use a short example of teaching
the students about Austin’s
theory of sovereignty. I sketched in the
social context as follows. I began by telling my students that Austin’s
theory provides
a description of British sovereignty in the 1830s, the time that
he was writing and just prior to the signing of the Treaty of
Waitangi.39 I noted that Austin’s work was
published only through the efforts of his wife, Sarah Austin, who supported him
all through
his life with her earnings as a writer and
translator.40 The original publication of the first
part of his lectures in 1832 received no notice outside Austin’s close
circle of friends.41 It was Sarah Austin who managed to
have the second edition of these lectures published posthumously in
1861.42 She also wrote up Lectures on
Jurisprudence or the Philosophy of Positive Law posthumously from his
notes and had that published in 1863.43 She wrote of
her husband that he lived “a life of unbroken disappointment and
failure.”44 Indeed, many critiques of Austin are
better known than his work.45
Why is the work of a
thoroughly critiqued failure studied in law schools over 100 years later? Sarah
Austin’s timing of the
second edition of Austin’s lectures in 1861
turned out to be fortuitous. It was between the first and second editions of his
lectures that law became a recognised subject in the Universities in England and
the second edition almost immediately became an
examination book at the
universities,46 ensuring widespread dissemination of
his ideas. His legacy is the resulting influence and considerable influence that
his work has
had in the subject of jurisprudence in England, and the manner in
which the ideas that he espoused facilitated British colonisation.
Austin
defined the sovereign as the unlimited ruler of one united independent political
society, meaning in part that the sovereign
is not answerable to anyone
else.47 He also states that kinship groups, such as
Native Americans, cannot constitute an independent political society, and
therefore,
according to his theory, cannot have a
sovereign.48
The legacy that Austin’s work
created in the political context of British colonisation is reflected in the
1877 New Zealand
case of Wi Parata v The Bishop of
Wellington.49 In this case Chief
Justice Prendergast stated that the Treaty of Waitangi was a “simple
nullity... [because] No body politic existed
capable of making session of
sovereignty...”, that is, because Maori people did not constitute an
independent political society
with a sovereign capable of ceding sovereignty.
This became the dominant interpretation of the Treaty in New Zealand until at
least
the 1980s, and some still argue for this interpretation
today.50 Although some contemporary New Zealand
academics now argue that Prendergast got the law wrong in
1877,51 his decision was not challenged successfully in
Court until the mid-1980s52 and in the meantime it
certainly facilitated British settlement of New Zealand. It legitimated over 100
pieces of legislation to
“legalise” Maori dispossession from Maori
land.53 It has been argued that all of these pieces of
legislation were enacted in breach of the Treaty.54
Today Maori people retain only 5 per cent of freehold land in New
Zealand.55
Judge Prendergast, who decided the Wi
Parafa case, studied law just after the second edition of Austin’s
work was published.56 It seems possible that he read
Austin then. Upon graduation, Prendergast had a difficult time getting work in
England (this is always
good for the students to know) so he moved to New
Zealand, where he became a judge in 1875.57 The
language from his decision in the Wi Parata case that I have quoted may
reflect the influence of Austin’s work. Even if Austin’s work did
not directly influence Prendergast,
it provides an example of a theory of
sovereignty espoused at a historical moment when the ideology and language of
sovereignty were
very strong.
Teaching Austin’s work in its social and
political context is an example of situating knowledge. Explicit recognition of
the
essential contributions of Sarah Austin to John Austin’s work and the
resulting influence of his work provides an example of
the crucial roles that
women have played throughout history in supporting the production of knowledge:
Austin’s theory was
not produced in a vacuum. Discussion of the reflection
of ideas about sovereignty such as those contained in Austin’s work
in an
influential New Zealand case makes the theory relevant to students in New
Zealand and integrates jurisprudence into the law
curriculum. The introduction
of Austin’s work provided the basis from which we then discussed the
current sovereignty debate
in New Zealand, some of which I have already
outlined.
Teaching Methods
I have discussed examples of the manner in which
feminist epistemologies influenced the design and substance of the University of
Waikato School of Law’s law-in-context jurisprudence course. I can touch
only briefly on methods in the classroom that addressed
feminist epistemologies.
To illustrate the situated aspects of knowledge, I placed a chair in the centre
of the U-shaped classroom.
I asked students sitting around the chair to sketch
it and to pass around their sketches. We discussed how the sketches were
different
depending on where the students were sitting in relation to the chair;
for example, some students in the back row had parts of the
chair obscured by
the people and tables in front of them. So the students’ perspectives on
the chair depended on where they
were placed in relation to the chair, and
although they might be able to crane their necks and get a bit better view, or
look at
the pictures drawn by people who were sitting in different places or
talk to those people about their pictures, or even change their
own position in
relation to the chair to some extent, they could never see all of the chair from
every perspective at once. As Donna
Haraway writes, “Relativism and
totalisation [or objectivity] are both ‘god-tricks’ promising vision
from everywhere
and nowhere equally and
fully...”58
Later in the course we also talk
about valuing perspectives on the chair. We discuss the rule of law and the
underlying myth of the
level playing field. If we do not start from a level
playing field then power imbalances are involved in distinguishing the
perspectives
on the chair — should we value the perspectives of the
powerful or the powerless? Does it depend on whether it is a chair that
we are
viewing or whether it is the oppression of the powerless that we are viewing? Is
the view from below the chair better? When?
To what extent do the powerful have
the resources to impose their views of the chair on those who are relatively
powerless? The discussion
of situated knowledges also provides the class with
one of many critical perspectives on the theorists discussed throughout the
year.
The extent to which each theorist identifies and analyses her or his own
perspective, and the effect this has on the credibility
of the theory, is
discussed. Students are also asked to consider and analyse their own
perspectives in the essays that they write
for the course.
CONCLUDING THOUGHTS
In conclusion, all knowledge is situated. Teaching involves the creation of knowledge. Attention to theories of knowledge and knowledge creation in teaching requires awareness of the partiality of knowledge, limitations in producing knowledge and the context in which knowledge is produced. Feminist epistemologies can be useful tools in developing strategies for teaching; focusing us as educators on the political and social context in which the knowledge we teach is produced, on the political and social context in which we re-produce the knowledge, on our own limitations in reproducing knowledge, and on methods for teaching our students about the situated aspects of knowledge. Feminist epistemologies present us with the imperative of uncloaking the prevailing myth of objectivity in the knowledge that we produce through teaching, and, therefore have implications for the ways in which we design all of our courses, for the substance of our courses and for the teaching methods that we use.
* Faculty of Law, University of Waikato .
© 1996. (1995) 6 Legal
Educ Rev 153
1 Susan Hekman, Gender and Knowledge: Elements of a Postmodern Feminism (Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1990); L Stanley & S Wise, Method, Methodology and Epistemology in Feminist Research, in L Stanley ed, Feminist Praxis: Research, Theory and Epistemology in Feminist Sociology (London: Routledge, 1990) 20–59; S Harding, Introduction: Is There a Feminist Method?, in S Harding ed, Feminism and Methodology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987).
2 KA Lahey, ... Until Women Themselves Have Told All That They Have To Tell... (1985) 23 Osgoode Hall LJ 525.
3 K Abrams, Hearing the Call of Stories (1991) 79 Cal L Rev 971, at 976.
4 Eg C MacKinnon, Towards a Feminist Theory of the State (New York: Routledge, 1989).
5 Eg D Cornell, The Philosophy of the Limit (New York: Routledge, 1992) 1–12.
6 J Scott, Experience, in J Butler & J Scott eds, Feminists Theorize the Political (New York: Routledge, 1992); D Fuss, Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature and Difference (New York: Routledge, 1989).
7 L Smith, Maori Women: Discourse, Projects and Mana Wahine, in S Middleton & A Jones eds, Women and Education in Aotearoa 2 (Wellington: Allen & Unwin, 1992); K Irwin, Towards Theories of Maori Feminisms, in R Du Plessis ed, Feminist Voices (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1992); A Harris, Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory (1990) 42 Stan L Rev 581; A Parashar, Essentialism or Pluralism: The Future of Legal Feminism (1993) 6 Can J Women 6 L 328; K Crenshaw, Mapping the Margins: intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color (1991) 43 Stan L Rev 1241; E Spelman, Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought (Boston: Beacon Press, 1988).
8 LE White, Paradox, Piece Work and Patience (1992) 43 Hastings LJ 853, at 855.
9 K Bartlett, Feminist Legal Methods (1990) 103 Harv L Rev 829, at 880; D Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1991) 188.
10 Experience is not a word we can do without ... [i]t serves as a way of talking about what happened, of establishing difference and similarity, of claiming knowledge that is “unassailable.” Given the ubiquity of the term, it seems more useful to work with it, to analyse its operations and to redefine its meaning. This entails focusing on processes of identity production, insisting on the discursive nature of “experience” and on the politics of construction. Experience is at once always already an interpretation and is in need of interpretation. What counts as experience is neither self-evident nor straightforward; it is always contested, always therefore political. (citation omitted) Scott, supra note 6, at 37.
11 Bartlett, supra note 9, at 880–881; Haraway, supra note 9, at 190.
12 Haraway, supra note 9, at 183–201.
13 Haraway, supra note 9, at 190–91.
14 Id at 190.
15 Id at 190.
16 Id at 190–191.
17 D Connell, Toward a Modern/Postmodern Reconstruction of Ethics (1985) 133 U Pa L Rev 291, at 378.
18 Haraway, supra note 9, at 191.
19 Id.
20 Id at 190.
21 Id at 190–191.
22 Harding, supra note 23, at 185; Harstock, supra note 23, at 157, 159–160.
23 Harding, supra note 23, at 185.
24 Id at 184–185, 188; Stanley, supra note l, at 27.
25 Bartlett, supra note 9, at 873–874.
“My effort here takes a similar form [to a Marxian analysis of capitalism] in an attempt to move toward a theory of the extraction and appropriation of women’s activity and women themselves. Still, I adopt this strategy with some reluctance, since it contains a danger of making invisible the experience of lesbians or women of colour. At the same time, I recognize that the effort to uncover a feminist standpoint assumes that there are some things common to all women’s lives in Western class societies.” (Citations omitted.) Harstock, supra note 23, at 164; see P Cain, Feminist Jurisprudence: Grounding the Theories (1989) 4 Berkeley Women’s LJ 191, at 213–214 (discussion of “lesbian standpoint”).
26 Haraway, supra note 9, at 196 “There is no single feminist standpoint because our maps require too many dimensions for that metaphor to ground our visions.”
27 Bartlett, supra note 9, at 873–874; but see CA Littleton Feminist Jurisprudence: The Difference Method Makes (1989) 41 Stan L Rev 751, at 771–784 (Littleton defends MacKinnon’s work against Bartlett’s critique that MacKinnon uses standpoint epistemology and that her work is therefore essentialist).
28 Haraway, supra note 9, at 190–191.
29 See R Frankenburg, White Women, Race Matters: The Social Construction of Whiteness (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993) 191–235 (a discussion of how it is in the interests of white women to be unaware of the privilege that they experience due to their race); CA MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987) 147 n 6 (“’Male’, which is an adjective here, is a social and political concept, not a biological attribute; it is a status conferred upon a person by a condition of birth. As I use ‘male,’ it has nothing to do with inherency, preexistence, nature, inevitability, or body as such. Because it is in the interest of men to be male in the system we live under (male being powerful as well as human), they seldom question its rewards or even see it as a status at all.”)
30 R Walker, The Treaty of Waitangi as the Focus of Maori Protest, in IH Kawharu ed, Waitangi: Maori and Pakeha Perspectives of the Treaty of Waitangi (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1989) 263, 263–269.
31 Eg M Jackson, The Maori and the Criminal Justice System — He Whaipaanga Hou: A New Perspective, Pt 1 (Wellington, Department of Justice, 1988) 264–279; Walker, supra note 32, at 263–269; E Taihakurei Durie & GS Orr, The Role of the Waitangi Tribunal and the Development of a Bicultural Jurisprudence (1990) 14 NZULR 62; S Jackson, Decolonising Aotearoa (1990) 9/10 Race Gender Class 42.
32 Walker, supra note 32, at 263–265.
33 Jackson, supra note 33.
34 Id at 265.
35 University of Waikato School of Law Handbook (1991) 7.
36 Eg Ngahuia Te Awekotuku, He Tikanga Whakaaro: Research Ethics in the Maori Community (Wellington: Manatu Maori, 1991).
37 A Mikaere, Book Review (1990) 14 NZULR 97, at 99.
38 M Jackson, The Treaty and the Word: The Colonization of Maori Philosophy, in G Oddie & R Perrett eds, Justice, Ethics and New Zealand Society (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1992) 9.
39 HLA Hart, Introduction, in John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1955) xi.
40 Id at viii-ix.
41 Id.
42 Id at ix.
43 Id.
44 Id at xvi.
45 Id at xi.
46 Id at xvii.
47 J Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1955) 193–194.
48 Id at 207–211.
49 (1877) 3 NZJR (NS) 72.
50 Eg G Chapman, The Treaty of Waitangi — fertile ground for judicial (and academic) myth making Duly 19911 NZLJ 228, at 231. Chapman notes regarding the Wi Parata decision, “In its clarity of exposition, and basic soundness of judgment, it is fitting testimony to the quality of that most learned Chief Justice’s judicial work.” Id.
51 F Hackshaw, Nineteenth Century Notions of Aboriginal Title and their Influence on the Interpretation of the Treaty of Waitangi, in IH Kawharu ed, Waitangi: Maori and Pakeha Perspectives of the Treaty of Waitangi (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1989) 92, 93 (“instead of reflecting established law, [Wi Parata] reflected untested positivist-inspired legal theories. ..”); FM Brookfield, The New Zealand Constitution: the search for legitimacy, in IH Kawharu ed, Waitangi : Maori and Pakeha Perspectives of the Treaty of Waitangi (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1989) 1, 10 (“the work done recently by academic writers ... appears to leave no doubt that since the late 1870s successive New Zealand judges have misunderstood the law... on the whole they did indeed get it wrong”); but compare D V Williams, Te Tititi o Waitangi — Unique Relationship Between Crown and Tangata Whenua?, in IH Kawharu ed, Waitangi: Maori and Pakeha Perspectives of the Treaty of Waitangi (Auckland, Oxford University Press, 1989) 64, 87 (referring to Wi Parata, “Modern legal scholars tend to be squeamish about such a transparent moulding of legal doctrine to suit the convenience of colonial capitalism, and no doubt the colonial judiciary did ‘misunderstand,’ deliberately or otherwise, the doctrine of aboriginal title ... colonial judges in many parts of the Empire were adept at reaching decisions convenient for colonial Governments which were at the expense of indigenous peoples’ rights.”)
52 New Zealand Maori Council v Attorney General [l987] 1 NZLR 641.
53 M Jackson, Land Loss and the Treaty of Waitangi, in Witi Ihimaera ed, To Ao Marama 2: Regaining Aotearoa (Auckland: Reed, 1993) 77.
54 Id.
55 P Havemann, “The Pakeha Constitutional Revolution?” Five Perspectives on Maori Rights and Pakeha Duties (1993) 1 Waikato LR 53, at 54.
56 WH Oliver, ed, The Dictionary of New Zealand Biography (Vol I) (Wellington: Allen and Unwin, Department of Internal Affairs, 1990) 354–355. In 1881 Prendergast sanctioned the raid on Parihaka. In November 1881 he was knighted,
57 Id.
58 Haraway, supra note 9, at 191.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/1995/8.html